Skip to main content
Log in

Functional homology and homology of function: biological concepts and philosophical consequences

  • Published:
Biology & Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

“Functional homology” appears regularly in different areas of biological research and yet it is apparently a contradiction in terms—homology concerns identity of structure regardless of form and function. I argue that despite this conceptual tension there is a legitimate conception of ‘homology of function’, which can be recovered by utilizing a distinction from pre-Darwinian physiology (use versus activity) to identify an appropriate meaning of ‘function’. This account is directly applicable to molecular developmental biology and shares a connection to the theme of hierarchy in homology. I situate ‘homology of function’ within existing definitions and criteria for structural assessments of homology, and introduce a criterion of ‘organization’ for judging function homologues, which focuses on hierarchically interconnected interdependencies (similar to relative position and connection for skeletal elements in structural homology). This analysis of biological concepts has at least three broad philosophical consequences: (1) it provides the grounds for the study of behavior and psychological categories as homologues; (2) it demonstrates that philosophers who take selected effect function as primary effectively ignore large portions of comparative, structural, and experimental research, thereby misconstruing biological reasoning and knowledge; and, (3) it underwrites causal generalizations, which illuminates inferences made from model organisms in experimental biology.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Many biological cases are tricky to interpret and the line between homology and analogy can be difficult to draw in practice, especially because of the hierarchical relationships among homologues and analogues (Hall 1994). The contrast class for homology is often taken to be more than analogy (convergent similarity of function due to selection). ‘Homoplasy’ encompasses analogy, reversal, parallelism, and other non-homologous phenomena (Hall 2003).

  2. Form is explicated in terms of the material composition and arrangement, shape or appearance of organic materials (Bock and von Wahlert 1965), whereas function picks out activities at any level of organization performed or displayed by organisms (Dullemeijer 1981).

  3. Strictly parallel language displays this dependence: ‘an organismal innovation is a function that is neither homologous to any function in the ancestral species nor operational elsewhere (serially homologous) in the functional context of the same organism’.

  4. Bock and von Wahlert (1965) made a similar distinction between ‘activity’ (what something does) and ‘biological role’ (what something is used for). I originally took their ‘activity’ to correspond to causal role functions (Love 2005, 2006), but now concur that they are distinct (see Wouters 2003: 642–3).

  5. This distinction came to my attention via an unpublished paper by Jim Lennox entitled “Biological function: a brief slice of history”. There is a third aspect, ‘movement’, which I am ignoring here.

  6. “Explanations of use and explanations of activity will refer to quite different sets of facts; and this is as true today as it was for Galen” (Furley and Wilkie 1984: 63).

  7. It should be stressed that the use vs. activity distinction is epistemological, which means that there need not be ‘bare’ activity-functions with no use-function. Rather, activity-functions can be described and investigated as such apart from their use-functions, whether causal role, viability, or selected effect. There can also be different descriptions of the same activity-function that may be more or less germane depending on which use-functions are in view.

  8. Activity-function homology and the nature of functional hierarchies are related to explorations of ‘process homology’ by Evo-devo researchers: “By a ‘process’ we refer to an action (what happens), not to its functional outcome (why it happens)” (Gilbert and Bolker 2001: 445; see also Brigandt, this issue).

  9. There is no privileged level of analysis; only the requirement that one is explicit about where you are trying to discern activity-function homologues. Thus, even though rhythmic muscular contraction is an activity that contributes to the causal role capacity of the heart pumping, heart pumping could be considered as an activity-function homologue in the causal role context of the cardiovascular system.

  10. One key explanation for this divergence in developmental role despite activity-function homology of DNA binding is that Hox genes work in tandem with other cofactors (Svingen and Tonissen 2006). Change in sequence outside of the DNA binding domain can lead to altered cofactor interaction, which implies that a regulatory gene can retain one activity-function homology and lose another.

  11. In recent literature, Gerd Müller (2003) has emphasized the importance of organization for structural homology and I have pursued this theme in an experimental context (Love and Raff 2006).

  12. This is also congruent with the argument that non-arbitrary individuations of causal role functions are secured by ascribing them only to systems exhibiting hierarchical organization (Davies 2001, ch. 4).

  13. Some candidates for activity-function homology are directly tied to particular structurally homologous features, such as homeodomain DNA sequence and the activity of DNA binding. A different asymmetry between structure and function arises in phylogenetic reconstruction, which leans heavily on structural data (e.g. skeletal anatomy or DNA sequences), even though activity-function character states can also be scored (i.e. functional characters can provide good phylogenetic data). This is a result of the greater difficulty in obtaining functional data as opposed to structural data (Lauder 1990). The dependence of homology of function on structural characters in this sense is indirect, mediated through the identification of structural synapomorphies required to construct a necessary but insufficient phylogenetic context.

  14. The success of activity-function homology is due in part to treating activities structurally (‘structure’=df “The mutual relation of the constituent parts or elements of a whole as determining its peculiar nature or character”; OED). I am intentionally skirting the ontological issue of whether there are both entities (structures) and activities (functions) or, alternatively, whether activities can be reduced to the interactions of entities (cf. Tabery 2004).

  15. “Every biologically interesting structure is labeled by the term that expresses its selected effect; how a structure is ‘individuated’—how the border between it and other structures in the same animal or plant (or fungi) are drawn—depends on its selected effect, its function” (Rosenberg 2006: 137).

  16. “Amundson and Lauder and perhaps also Griffiths seem to maintain that there are not functional categories of any scientific significance in biology, with the exception of the analogous categories being categories of traits that have evolved independently to serve the same function” (Neander 2002: 391). This is a strange assertion because all three of these authors clearly state that causal role functional categories are ubiquitous in experimental biology. Only selected effect functional categories are identified with evolutionary analogies, which follows the mainstream neo-Darwinian tradition.

  17. “We investigated functional conservation among the Drosophila zinc-finger homeodomain protein 1 (zfh1) and its mouse functional homologue Smad-interacting protein 1 (SIP1)” (Liu et al. 2006: 683).

  18. Vertebrate lens crystallins could be used to explore some of these issues (Piatigorsky 2007). The enzymatic activity of aldehyde dehydrogenase in different taxa can be activity-function homologous but its role as a transparent, refractive globular protein in the eye usually is not. This is because different metabolic enzymes (e.g. transketolase) and stress protection proteins (e.g. heat shock) were recruited into the role of lens crystallins in different vertebrate taxa because they also could play the role of a transparent, refractive globular protein, and thus lens crystallins as a class are most likely to be activity-function analogues.

References

  • Abouheif E (1997) Developmental genetics and homology: a hierarchical approach. Trends Ecol Evol 12:405–408

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Abouheif E, Akam M, Dickinson WJ, Holland PWH, Meyer A, Patel NH, Raff RA, Roth VL, Wray GA (1997) Homology and developmental genes. Trends Genet 13:432–433

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Amos LA, van den Ent F, Löwe J (2004) Structural/functional homology between the bacterial and eukaryotic cytoskeletons. Curr Opin Cell Biol 16:24–31

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Amundson R, Lauder GV (1994) Function without purpose: the uses of causal role function in evolutionary biology. Biol Philos 9:443–470

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Allen C, Bekoff M, Lauder GV (eds) (1998) Nature’s purposes: analyses of function and design in biology. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Ariew A, Cummins R, Perlman M (eds) (2002) Functions: new essays in the philosophy of psychology and biology. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel W, Richardson R (1993) Discovering complexity: decomposition and localization as strategies in scientific research. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Bock WJ, von Wahlert G (1965) Adaptation and the form-function complex. Evolution 19:269–299

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boyd R, Richerson PJ, Borgerhoff-Mulder M, Durham WH (2005) [1997], Are cultural phylogenies possible? In: Boyd R, Richerson PJ (eds) The origin and evolution of cultures. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 310–336

  • Brigandt I (2002) Homology and the origin of correspondence. Biol Philos 17:389–407

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brigandt I (2003) Homology in comparative, molecular, and evolutionary developmental biology: the radiation of a concept. J Exp Zoolog (Mol Dev Evol) 299B:9–17

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brigandt I (2006) Homology and heterochrony: the evolutionary embryologist Gavin Rylands de Beer (1899–1972). J Exp Zoolog (Mol Dev Evol) 306B:317–328

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davies PS (2001) Norms of nature: naturalism and the nature of functions. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Donoghue MJ (1992) Homology. In: Keller EF, Lloyd EA (eds) Keywords in evolutionary biology. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA, pp 170–179

    Google Scholar 

  • Dullemeijer P (1981) Functional morphology and evolutionary biology. Acta Biotheor 29:151–250

    Google Scholar 

  • Facchin S, Lopreiato R, Ruzzene M, Marin O, Sartori G, Götz C, Montenarh M, Carignani G, Pinna LA (2003) Functional homology between yeast piD261/Bud32 and human PRPK: both phosphorylate p53 and PRPK partially complements piD261/Bud32 deficiency. FEBS Lett 549:63–66

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Furley D, Wilkie JS (eds) (1984) Galen: on respiration and the arteries. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Ghiselin MT (2005) Homology as a relation of correspondence between parts of individuals. Theory Biosci 124:91–103

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert SF, Bolker JA (2001) Homologies of process and modular elements of embryonic construction. In: Wagner GP (ed) The character concept in evolutionary biology. Academic Press, San Diego, pp 437–456

    Google Scholar 

  • Greene HW (1994) Homology and behavioral repertoires. In: Hall BK (ed) Homology: the hierarchical basis of comparative biology. Academic Press, San Diego, pp 369–391

    Google Scholar 

  • Greene HW, Burghardt GM (1978) Behavior and phylogeny: constriction in ancient and modern snakes. Science 200:74–77

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths PE (1997) What emotions really are: the problem of psychological categories. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths PE (2006) Function, homology, and character individuation. Philos Sci 73:1–25

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths PE (2007) Evo-devo meets the mind: towards a developmental evolutionary psychology. In: Sansom R, Brandon RN (eds) Integrating development and evolution: from theory to practice. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Gulledge AT, Kawaguchi Y (2007) Phasic cholinergic signaling in the hippocampus: functional homology with the neocortex? Hippocampus 17:327–332

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hall BK (ed) (1994) Homology: the hierarchical basis of comparative biology. Academic Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Hall BK (2003) Descent with modification: the unity underlying homology and homoplasy as seen through an analysis of development and evolution. Biol Rev Camb Philos Soc 78:409–433

    Google Scholar 

  • Hanken J (1993) Model systems versus outgroups: alternative approaches to the study of head development and evolution. Am Zool 33:448–456

    Google Scholar 

  • Hauser M (2005) Our chimpanzee mind. Nature 437:60–63

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hotamisligil G (2006) Inflammation and metabolic disorders. Nature 444:860–867

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huang A, Scougall CA, Lowenthal JW, Jilbert AR, Kotlarski I (2001) Structural and functional homology between duck and chicken interferon-gamma. Dev Comp Immunol 25:55–68

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johansson I, Smith B, Munn K, Tsikolia N, Elsner K, Ernst D, Siebert D (2005) Functional anatomy: a taxonomic proposal. Acta Biotheor 53:153–166

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lauder GV (1990) Functional morphology: studying functional patterns in an historical context. Annu Rev Ecol Syst 21:317–340

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lauder GV (1994) Homology, form, and function. In: Hall BK (ed) Homology: the hierarchical basis of comparative biology. Academic Press, Inc., San Diego, pp 151–196

    Google Scholar 

  • Lauder GV (1995) On the inference of function from structure. In: Thomason JJ (ed) Functional morphology in vertebrate paleontology. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 1–18

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewens T (2004) Organisms and artifacts: design in nature and elsewhere. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Liu M, Su M, Lyons GE, Bodmer R (2006) Functional conservation of zinc-finger homeodomain gene zfh1/SIP1 in Drosophila heart development. Dev Genes Evol 216:683–693

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Love AC (2005) Explaining evolutionary innovation and novelty: a historical and philosophical study of biological concepts. PhD Thesis, University of Pittsburgh, Department of History and Philosophy of Science

  • Love AC (2006) Evolutionary morphology and Evo-devo: hierarchy and novelty. Theory Biosci 124:317–333

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Love AC The hedgehog, the fox, and reductionism in biology. Evolution, doi: 10.1111/j.1558-5646.2007.00228.x

  • Love AC, Raff RA (2006) Larval ectoderm, organizational homology, and the origins of evolutionary novelty. J Exp Zoolog (Mol Dev Evol) 306B:18–34

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Manak JR, Scott MP (1994) A class act: conservation of homeodomain protein functions. Dev Suppl 61–71

  • Millikan R (1989) In defense of proper functions. Philos Sci 56:288–302

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Müller GB (2003) Homology: the evolution of morphological organization. In: Müller GB, Newman SA (eds) Origination of organismal form: beyond the gene in developmental and evolutionary biology. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, pp 51–69

    Google Scholar 

  • Müller GB, Wagner GP (1991) Novelty in evolution: restructuring the concept. Annu Rev Ecol Syst 22:229–256

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neander K (1991) Functions as selected effects: the conceptual analyst’s defense. Philos Sci 58:168–184

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neander K (2002) Types of traits: the importance of functional homologues. In: Ariew A, Cummins R, Perlman M (eds) Functions: new essays in the philosophy of biology and psychology. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 390–415

    Google Scholar 

  • Nishikawa K, Biewener AA, Aerts P, Ahn AN, Chiel HJ, Daley MA, Daniel TL, Full RJ, Hale ME, Hedrick TL, Lappin AK, Nichols TR, Quinn RD, Satterlie RA, Szymik B (2007) Neuromechanics: an integrative approach for understanding motor control. Integr Comp Biol 47:16–54

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nozaki M, Gorbman A (1992) The question of functional homology of Hatschek’s pit of amphioxus (Branchiostoma belcheri) and the vertebrate adenohypophysis. Zool Sci 9:387–395

    Google Scholar 

  • Owen R (1843) Lectures on the comparative anatomy and physiology of the invertebrate animals. Longman, Brown, Green, and Longmans, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Pabst DA (2000) To bend a dolphin: convergence of force transmission designs in cetaceans and scombrid fishes. Am Zool 40:146–155

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Piatigorsky J (2007) Gene sharing and evolution: the diversity of protein functions. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Pohl BS, Knöchel W (2005) Of Fox and frogs: Fox (fork head/winged helix) transcription factors in Xenopus development. Gene 344:21–32

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ranganayakulu G, Elliott DA, Harvey RP, Olson EN (1998) Divergent roles for NK-2 class homeobox genes in cardiogenesis in flies and mice. Development 125:3037–3048

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenberg A (2006) Darwinian reductionism: or, how to stop worrying and love molecular biology. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Schlosser G, Wagner GP (eds) (2004) Modularity in development and evolution. University of Chicago Press, Chicago and London

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwenk K (2001) Functional units and their evolution. In: Wagner GP (ed) The character concept in evolutionary biology. Academic Press, San Diego, pp 167–200

    Google Scholar 

  • Svingen T, Tonissen KF (2006) Hox transcription factors and their elusive mammalian gene targets. Heredity 97:88–96

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tabery JG (2004) Synthesizing activities and interactions in the concept of a mechanism. Philos Sci 71:1–15

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vázquez-Novelle MD, Esteban V, Bueno A, Sacristán MP (2005) Functional homology among human and fission yeast Cdc14 phosphatases. J Biol Chem 280:29144–29150

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wagner GP (eds) (2001) The character concept in evolutionary biology. Academic Press, San Diego

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber M (2005) Philosophy of experimental biology. Cambridge University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Wenzel JW (1992) Behavioral homology and phylogeny. Annu Rev Ecol Syst 23:361–381

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt WC (2002) Functional organization, analogy, and inference. In: Ariew A, Cummins R, Perlman M (eds) Functions: new essays in the philosophy of psychology and biology. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 173–221

    Google Scholar 

  • Wouters A (2003) Four notions of biological function. Stud Hist Philos Biol Biomed Sci 34:633–668

    Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt WC (2005) The function debate in philosophy. Acta Biotheor 53:123–151

    Google Scholar 

  • Wray GA (1999) Evolutionary dissociations between homologous genes and homologous structures. In: Bock GR, Cardew G (eds) Homology. Wiley, Chichester, pp 189–206

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Alan C. Love.

Additional information

This paper benefited greatly from the feedback of participants at the 2006 Philosophy and Developmental Biology Workshop in Vancouver and those attending the ‘The Importance of Homology for Biology and Philosophy’ session at the 2007 ISHPSSB in Exeter. Ingo Brigandt, Marc Ereshefsky, Paul Griffiths, Mohan Matthen, and Karola Stotz provided helpful suggestions on many aspects of an earlier version of the paper. I am also grateful to Marc Ereshefsky for organizing these symposia on homology, which spurred me to work on this material.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Love, A.C. Functional homology and homology of function: biological concepts and philosophical consequences. Biol Philos 22, 691–708 (2007). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-007-9093-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-007-9093-7

Keywords

Navigation