Skip to main content
Log in

Schizophrenia and the Place of Egodystonic States in the Aetiology of Thought Insertion

  • Published:
Review of Philosophy and Psychology Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Despite the diagnostic relevance of thought insertion for disorders such as schizophrenia, the debates about its aetiology are far from resolved. This paper claims that in paying exclusive attention to the perceptual and cognitive impairments leading to delusional experiences in general, current deficit approaches overlook the role that affective disturbances might play in giving rise to cases of thought insertion. In the context of psychosis, affective impairments are often characterized as a consequence of the stress and anxiety caused by delusional episodes. However, here I explore some of the conceptual and empirical reasons to think that affective problems might in fact play a crucial doxastic role in the aetiology of thought insertion. Finally, I conclude by proposing a way of integrating the main insights of my analysis with the current ‘two-factor’ deficit approach to thought insertion and I explore the potential adaptive role that some delusions might have within this framework.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. In this context, by ‘adaptive’ I simply mean ‘beneficial’ in any way for the patient’s life. For a further discussion of this issue, see: McKay and Dennett (2009); Bortolotti (2014)).

  2. As we will see in the last section, I do not consider these approaches as completely incompatible.

  3. One of the weaknesses of Butler’s position is that its primary interest is with a very specific and rare delusion. Therefore, it is not entirely clear if his conclusions can be extrapolated to the analysis of other delusions.

  4. It is widely granted among psychotherapists that a good quality psychotherapeutic intervention should use the patient’s own psychological resources and biographically relevant elements for the intervention to be meaningful (see Guidano 1991; Arciero and Bondolfi 2010).

  5. This hypothesis is attributed to Snyder (1974).

  6. I thank one of the anonymous referees for pointing out this issue

  7. It is important to note that most approaches to delusions have overlooked the examination of the role that the context of the occurrence might have in the aetiology of delusional episodes

  8. Interestingly, this idea resembles the way in which the TAH explains the first stage of the occurrence of inserted thoughts (Section 3).

References

  • Aiello, G., M. Horowitz, N. Hepgul, C.M. Pariante, and V. Mondelli. 2012. Stress abnormalities in individuals at risk for psychosis: a review of studies in subjects with familial risk or with “at risk” mental state. Psychoneuroendocrinology 37: 1600–1613.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arciero, G., and G. Bondolfi. 2010. Selfhood, Identity and personality styles. UK: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bayne, T., and J. Fernández (eds.). 2009. Delusions and Self deception: Affective and Motivational Influences on Belief-Formation. Hove: Psychology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bayne, T., and E. Pacherie. 2004. Bottom up or top down? Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology 11(1): 1–11.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Birchwood, M. 2003. Pathways to emotional dysfunction in first-episode psychosis. British Journal of Psychiatry 182: 373–375.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bortolotti, L. (2014). The epistemic innocence of motivated delusions. Consciousness & Cognition. Online first: http://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S1053810014001937.

  • Butler, P.V. 2000. Reverse Othello syndrome subsequent a traumatic brain injury. Psychiatry: Interpersonal & Biological Processes 63(1): 85–92.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bentall, R., and S. Kaney. 1996. Abnormalities of self‑representation and persecutory delusions: a test of cognitive model of paranoia. Psychological Medicine 26: 1231–1237.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Broome, M.R., F. Day, I. Valli, et al. 2012. Delusional ideation, manic symptomatology and working memory in a cohort at clinical high-risk for psychosis: a longitudinal study. European Psychiatry 27: 258–263.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Broome, M.R., J.B. Woolley, P. Tabraham, et al. 2005. What causes the onset of psychosis? Schizophrenia Research 79: 23–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buckley, P.F., B.J. Miller, D.S. Lehrer, and D.J. Castle. 2009. Psychiatric comorbidities and schizophrenia. Schizophrenia Bulletin 35: 383–402.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, J. 1999. Schizophrenia, the space of reasons and thinking as a motor process. The Monist 82: 609–625.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Caponi, R. 2010. Psicopatología Semiología Psiquiatrica. Santiago: Universitaria.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coltheart, M. 2005. Delusional belief. Australian Journal of Psychology 57: 72–76.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coltheart, M., R. Langdon, and R. McKay. 2007. Schizophrenia and monothematic delusions. Schizophrenia Bulletin 33(3): 642–647.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davies, M. 2008. Delusion and motivationally biased belief: self deception in the two factor framework. In Delusion and Self deception: Affective and Motivational Influences on Belief Formation, ed. T. Bayne and J. Fernández, 71–86. Hove: Psychology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davies, M., M. Coltheart, R. Langdon, and N. Breen. 2001. Monothematic delusions: towards a two- factor account. Philosophy, Psychiatry and Psychology 8(2/3): 133–158.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, H.D., and A.W. Young. 1990. Accounting for delusional misidentifications. British Journal of Psychiatry 157: 239–248.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fine, C., J. Craigie, and I. Gold. 2005. The explanation approach to delusion. Philosophy, Psycjiatry & Psychology 12(2): 159–163.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fish, F.J. (1962). Fish’s Schizophrenia, third edition. Ed. M. Hamilton. Wright.

  • Frankish, K. 2011. Delusions, levels of belief, and non-doxastic acceptances. Neuroethics. doi:10.1007/s12152-011-9123-7.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fuchs, T. 2013. The phenomenology of affectivity. In The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy and Psychiatry, ed. K. Fulford, M. Davies, R. Gipps, G. Graham, J. Sadler, G. Stanghellini, and T. Thornton, 221–239. Oxford: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fuchs, T. 2005. Delusional mood and delusional perception. A phenomenological analysis. Psychopathology 38: 133–139. doi:10.1159/000085843.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Freud, S. 1961. Civilization and its discontents. New York: Norton.

  • Frijda, N. 1986. The Emotions. Cambridge (UK): Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frith, C.D. 1992. The cognitive neuropsychology of schizophrenia. Hoeve: Lawrennce Erlbaum Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. 2004. Neurocognitive models of schizophrenia. A neurophenomenological critique. Psychopathology 37: 8–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gibbs, P. 2000. Thought insertion and the inseparability thesis. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology 7(3): 195–202.

    Google Scholar 

  • Graham, G., and G.L. Stephens. 1994. Mind and mine. In Philosophical Psychology, ed. G. Graham and G. Stephens, 91–109. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guidano, V.F. 1991. The Self in Progress. New York: Guilford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Häfner, H., K. Maurer, and W. der Heiden. 2013. ABC Schizophrenia study: an overview of results since 1996. Social Psychiatry and Psychiatric Epidemiology 48: 1021–1031.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hamilton, M.A. (ed.). 1984. Fish’s schizophrenia. Bristol: Wright.

    Google Scholar 

  • Henry, J.D., P.G. Rendell, M.J. Green, S. McDonald, and M. O’Donnell. 2008. Emotion regulation in schizophrenia: affective, social, and clinical correlates of suppression and reappraisal. Journal of Abnormal Psychology 117: 473–478.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jaspers, K. 1963. General Psychopathology, 7th ed. Manchester: Manchester University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kramer, I., C. Simons, L. Wigman, et al. 2013. Time-lagged moment-to-moment interplay between negative affect and paranoia: new insights in the affective pathway to psychosis. Schizophrenia Bulletin 40(2): 278–286.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kinderman, P., and R.P. Bentall. 1996. Self-discrepancies and persecutory delusions: evidence for a model of paranoid ideation. Journal of Abnormal Psychology 105: 106–113.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kinderman, P., and R.P. Bentall. 1997. Causal attributions in paranoia and depression: internal, personal, and situational attributions for negative events. Journal of Abnormal Psychology 106: 341–345.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Langdon, R., and M. Coltheart. 2000. The cognitive neuropsychology of delusions. In Pathologies of Belief, ed. M. Coltheart and M. Davies, 183–216. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maiese, M. 2014. Thought insertion as a disownership symptom. Phenomenology & the Cognitive Sciences. doi:10.1007/s11097-014-9387-6.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maher, B.A. 1974. Delusional thinking and perceptual disorder. Journal of Individual Psychology 30: 98–113.

  • Maher, B.A. 2003. Schizophrenia, aberrant utterance and delusions of control: the disconnection of speech and thought, and the connection of experience and belief. Mind & Language 18: 1–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKay, R., R. Langdon, and M. Colheart. 2008. Sleights of mind: Delusions, and self deception. In Delusion and Self deception: Affective and Motivational Influences on Belief Formation, ed. T. Bayne and J. Fernàndez, 165–186. Hove: Psychology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McKay, R., and D. Dennett. 2009. The evolution of misbelief. Behavioural and Brain Sciences 32(6): 493–561.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martin, J.-M., and E. Pacherie. 2013. Out of nowhere: thought insertion, ownership and context-integration. Consciousness and Cognition 22(1): 111–122.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martens, W.H. 2002. Mental disorders as possible intrapsychic routes to remission. Part I: delusional and psychotic disorders. Medical Hypotheses 58(6): 503–508.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marwaha, S., M. Broome, P. Bebbington, E. Kuipers, and D. Freeman. 2013. Mood Instability and Psychosis: Analyses of British National Survey Data. Schizophrenia Bulletin, Published online first: http://schizophreniabulletin.oxfordjournals.org/content/early/2013/10/25/schbul.sbt149.short doi:10.1093/schbul/sbt149.

  • Mellor, C.S. 1970. First Rank symptoms of schizophrenia. The British Journal of Psychiatry 117: 15–23.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mullins, S., and S. Spence. 2003. Re-examining thought insertion. British Journal of Psychiatry 182: 293–298.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nayani, T., and A. David. 1996. The auditory hallucination. Psychological Medicine 26: 177–189.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Driscoll, C., J. Laing, and O. Mason. 2014. Cognitive emotion regulation strategies, alexithymia and dissociation in schizophrenia, a review and meta-analysis. Clinical Psychology Review. doi:10.1016/j.cpr.2014.07.002.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pacherie, E. 2008. Perceptions, Emotions, and Delusions: The Case of Capgras Delusion. In Delusion and Self deception: Affective and Motivational Influences on Belief Formation, ed. T. Bayne and J. Fernàndez, 107–126. Hove: Psychology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parnas, J., and P. Handest. 2003. Phenomenology of Anomalous Self-Experience in Early Schizophrenia. Comprehensive Psychiatry 44(2): 121–134.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Payne, E. 2013. Speaking to my Madness. USA: CreateSpace.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pickard, H. 2010. Schizophrenia and the epistemology of self-knowledge. European Journal of Analytic Philosophy 6(1): 55–74.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ramachandran, V.S. 1995. Anosognosia in parietal lobe syndrome. Consciousness & Cognition 4(1): 22–51.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ramachandran, V.S., and S. Blakeslee. 1998. Phantoms in the Brain: Human Nature and the Architecture of the Mind. London: Fourth Estate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roberts, G. 1992. The origin of delusions. The British Journal of Psychiatry 161: 298–308. doi:10.1192/bjp.161.3.298.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saks, E.R. 2007. The centre cannot hold. My journey through madness. New York: Hyperion.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sass, L.A. 1992. Madness and modernism: Insanity in the light of modern art, literature, and thought. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skodlar, B., et al. 2012. Cognitive-behavioral therapy for schizophrenia: a critical evaluation of its theoretical framework from a clinical-phenomenological perspective. Psychopathology 46: 249–265.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, A.C. 1982. Schizophrenia and madness. London: George Allen and Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Snyder, S. 1974. Madness and the brain. New York: McGraw-Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spence, S.A., D.J. Brooks, S.R. Hirsch, et al. 1997. APET study of voluntary movement in schizophrenic patients experiencing passivity phenomena (delusions of alien control). Brain 120: 1997–2001.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stephens, G.L., and G. Graham. 2000. When Self-Consciousness Breaks: Alien Voices and Inserted Thoughts. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strauss, G.P., E.S. Kappenman, A.J. Culbreth, L.T. Catalano, B.G. Lee, and J.M. Gold. 2013. Emotion regulation abnormalities in schizophrenia: cognitive change strategies fail to decrease the neural response to unpleasant stimuli. Schizophrenia Bulletin 39: 872–883.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stone, T., and A. Young. 1997. Delusions and brain injury. The philosophy and psychology of belief. Mind and Language 12: 327–364.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Synofzik, M., G. Vosgerau, and A. Newen. 2008. I move, therefore I am: a new theoretical framework to investigate agency and ownership. Consciousness and Cognition 17: 411–424.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Rossum, I., M.D. Dominguez, R. Lieb, H.U. Wittchen, and J. van Os. 2011. Affective dysregulation and reality distortion: a 10-year prospective study of their association and clinical relevance. Schizophrenia Bulletin 37: 561–571.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walsh, E., D. Oakley, P. Halligan, M. Mehta, and Q. Deeley. 2014. The functional anatomy and connectivity of thought insertion and alien control of movement. Cortex. doi:10.1016/j.cortex.2014.09.012.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank to Dr Joel Smith, Prof Tim Bayne, Prof Dr Thomas Fuchs, and the two anonymous referees provided by the journal for helpful comments on sections of this paper. Preliminary versions were presented in Symposium: From mental illness to disorder and diversity of the Meeting of The Society for the Study of Artificial Intelligence and Simulation of Behaviour (AISB), University of Kent (United Kingdom), and at the Heidelberg University Clinic for General Psychiatry ‘Kolloquium der Sektion Phänomenologie’ (Germany).

Financial support

The writing of this paper has been supported by the BECAS-CHILE programme of the National Commission for Science and Technology, CONICYT (Government of Chile), and partially supported by the Deutscher Akademischer Austausch Dienst (DAAD) Scholarship for Young Researchers.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Pablo López-Silva.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

López-Silva, P. Schizophrenia and the Place of Egodystonic States in the Aetiology of Thought Insertion. Rev.Phil.Psych. 7, 577–594 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-015-0272-1

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-015-0272-1

Keywords

Navigation