Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Authority, Autonomy and Automation: The Irreducibility of Pedagogy to Information Transactions

  • Published:
Studies in Philosophy and Education Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper draws attention to the tendency of a range of technologies to reduce pedagogical interactions to a series of datafied transactions of information. This is problematic because such transactions are always by definition reducible to finite possibilities. As the ability to gather and analyse data becomes increasingly fine-grained, the threat that these datafied approaches over-determine the pedagogical space increases. Drawing on the work of Hegel, as interpreted by twentieth century French radical philosopher Alexandre Kojève, this paper develops a model of relational pedagogy which highlights three points of incompatibility with a datafied learning environment reduced to finite measures. Firstly: Kojève’s accont of authority in Hegel posits two aspects to the mimetic relation between teacher and student: recognition and realisation, which belong to the ipseity or about-self-ness of the subject, and are incompatible with a general definition of data. Secondly, the Hegelian approach to human historical time, in particular the assertion that time and desire are begun in the future, not the past, renders it incompatible with mathematical time as used in data processing. Finally, from these it is possible to derive a distinctive notion of the work of pedagogy, grounded in Kojève’s realist reading of Hegel, irreducible to information processing. In consequence of this threefold irreducibility, the paper draws attention to a need for relations of human pedagogical work to be inherent in the design of educational technologies and highlights the dangers of presuming a machine intelligence model in the design of learning environments.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Indeed, in a radical attempt to assert the completion of the Hegelian conception of history, Kojève in his later work begins to lose signt of this, himself positing something akin to the penurious notion of interchangeable call-authenticate recognition (Kojève 2000) with the same penurious consequences for the project of self-becoming.

  2. Following the Second World War, the question of a just or proper authority is rendered absurd by the atrocities of its exercise. Empirical findings in cognitive and individual psychology begin to pathologies the ‘authoritarian personality’ (Adorno et al. 1950) while Anglophone political philosophy reorients toward questions of economy and distributive justice (Rawls 2009; Nozick 1973) or community and identity (Sandel 1998; Nussbaum 2004). Kojève, both in 1942 and in his mature work in subsequent decades, is somewhat exceptional, perhaps anachronistic, in still clearly addressing the same central question of authority in politics which animated Aristotle, Hobbes and Rousseau’s analyses in previous centuries.

  3. Justice (the locus of authority of the judge) and recognition (the Hegelian locus of authority of the master) are to be distinguished from one another precisely in regard to the interchangeability of mediation. While all authorities are socially mediated (Pippin 1993), justice requires impartiality. Kojève’s emphasis on the dependence of philosophical concept on human historical possibility leads him in his later work to the conclusion that the revolution and the end of history, as theorised by Hegel, had already arrived. While this attempt to presage a final reduction and resolution to the Hegelian dialectic proves unconvincing, it is not entirely penurious for the argument advanced in this paper. The characterisation of Kojève as ‘romantic bureaucrat’, concerned primarily with the administration of authority-as-justice in established conditions of universal mutual recognition introduces the thesis that the sage-philosopher and the administrator have a shared work of making manifest this ‘ideal’ reality in the material social conditions of the polis (Groys 2013). Under such an understanding, even should the first two incompatibilities—that of recognition/authentication and human-historical/processing time—be resolved, the critique that human (and specifically pedagogical) work is irreducibly distinct from machine work, remains valid.

References

  • Adorno, T., E. Frenkel-Brunswik, D. Levinson, and R. Sanford. 1950. The authoritarian personality. New York: Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Agiomavritis, D. 2012. A Polanyian deconstruction of Kojève’s vision of justice and globalisation. Modern Age 54: 1–4.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bailey, L.W. 2005. The enchantments of technology. Chicago, IL: University of Illinois Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benkler, Y. 2013. The Penguin and the Leviathan: The triumph of cooperation over self-interest. New York: Crown Business.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barden, O. 2014. Winking at Facebook: Capturing digitally mediated classroom learning. E-Learning and Digital Media 11(6): 554–568.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. 1984. Matter and consciousness: A contemporary introduction to the philosophy of mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Conroy, J. 2004. Betwixt and between: The liminal imagination, education and democracy. New York: Peter Lang.

    Google Scholar 

  • Conroy, J., D. Lundie, R.A. Davis, V. Baumfield, L.P. Barnes, T. Gallagher, K. Lowden, N. Bourque, and K. Wenell. 2013. Does religious education work? A multi-dimensional investigation. London: Bloomsbury Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crawford, M. 2015. The world beyond your head: On becoming an individual in an age of distraction. New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dickens, J. 2015. New software launched for teachers to spy on pupils at risk of radicalisation. [online] Available at: http://schoolsweek.co.uk/new-software-for-teachers-to-spy-on-pupils-at-risk-of-radicalisation-could-shut-down-terrorism-debate-in-schools/. [Accessed 27 July 2015].

  • Dretske, F. 1981. Knowledge and the flow of information. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ferguson, H. 2006. Desire, passion and self-surrender. Barcelona: Centre de Cultura Contemporània de Barcelona.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fetzer, J.H. 2004. The Philosophy of A.I. and its Critique. In Blackwell guide to the philosophy of computing and information, ed. L. Floridi, 117–134. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Floridi, L. 2004. Information. In The Blackwell guide to the philosophy of computing and information, ed. L. Floridi, 40–62. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Floridi, L. 2013. The ethics of information. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Groys, B. 2013. European graduate school video lectures. [online] Available at: https://youtu.be/9_O2T_xFJBo. [Accessed 7 July 2015].

  • Guilherme, A. 2014. Reflexions on Buber’s ‘living-centre’: Conceiving of the teacher as ‘the builder’ and teaching as a ‘situational revelation’. Studies in Philosophy and Education 34(3): 245–262.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, J. 2015. Humans need not apply: A guide to wealth and work in the age of artificial intelligence. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kojève, A. 1969. Introduction to the reading of Hegel: Lectures on the phenomenology of spirit. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kojève, A. 2000. Outline of a phenomenology of right. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kojève, A. 2014. The notion of authority, eBook ed. London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kroll, L. 2012. Gates foundation responds to GSR bracelets controversy. [online] Available at: http://www.forbes.com/sites/luisakroll/2012/06/13/gates-foundation-responds-to-gsr-bracelets-controversy/. [Accessed 19 June 2015].

  • Lewin, D. 2016. Humanising online pedagogy: Attention and education. Studies in Philosophy and Education.

  • Lundie, D. 2014. Educational Technology, the Philosophy of Information and the Education of the Human. In New directions in philosophy of education, ed. D. Lewin, and M. White. London: Bloomsbury Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lundie, D. 2015a. The Givenness of the Human Learning Experience and its Incompatibility with Information Analytics. Educational Philosophy and Theory.

  • Lundie, D. 2015b. Theorizing Relational Privacy: Embodied perspectives to support ethical professional pedagogies. In International handbook of interpretation in educational research, ed. P. Smeyers, D. Bridges, N. Burbules, and M. Griffiths, 1481–1498. Amsterdam: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marion, J.-L. 2002. Being given: Toward a phenomenology of givenness. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marion, J.-L. 2003. The original otherness of the ego: A rereading of Descartes Meditatio II. In The ethical, ed. E. Wyschgood, and G. McKenny, 33–53. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • McEwen, A., and H. Cassimally. 2014. Designing the internet of things. Chichester: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nozick, R. 1973. Distributive justice. Philosophy & Public Affairs 3: 45–126.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M. 2004. Liberal education and global community. Liberal Education 90(1): 42–47.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Connell, C. 2015. An examination of global university rankings as a new mechanism influencing mission differentiation: The UK context. Tertiary Education and Management 21(2): 111–126.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Penrose, R. 1989. The emperor’s new mind: Concerning computers, minds and the laws of physics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peters, R.S. 1966. Ethics and education. London: George Allen and Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pippin, R. 1993. Being, time, and politics: The Strauss–Kojève debate. History and Theory 32(2): 138–161.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rancière, J. 1991. The ignorant schoolmaster: Five lessons in intellectual emancipation. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. 2009. A theory of justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ricoeur, P. 1976. Interpretation theory: Discourse and the surplus of meaning. Fort Worth, TX: Christian University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rumelhart, D. 1986. Parallel distributed processing: Explorations in the microstructure of cognition. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sandel, M. 1998. Liberalism and the limits of justice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sclater, N., and M. MacDonald. 2004. Putting interoperability to the test: Building a large reusable assessment item bank. ALT-J Research in Learning Technology 12(3): 205–213.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. 1980. Minds, brains and programs. Behavior and Brain Sciences 3: 417–457.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Siemens, G., et al. 2011. Open learning analytics: An integrated and modularized platform. s.l.: Society for Learning Analytics Research.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spencer, G. 1996. Microcybernetics as the meta-technology of pure control. In Cyberfutures: Culture and politics on the information superhighway, ed. Z. Sardar, and J.R. Ravetz, 61–76. London: Pluto Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steels, L. 2008. The symbol grounding problem has been solved, so what’s next? Symbols, embodiment and meaning. New Haven, CT: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strauss, L. 1991. On tyranny. New York: S.N.

    Google Scholar 

  • Trifonas, P. 2002. Revolutionary pedagogies: Cultural politics, education, and discourse of theory. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Urquhart, A. 2004. Complexity. In The Blackwell guide to the philosophy of computing and information, ed. L. Floridi, 18–27. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolpe, P.R., K.R. Foster, and D.D. Langleben. 2005. Emerging neurotechnologies for Lie Detection: Promises and perils. The American Journal of Bioethics 5(2): 39–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. 1999. Self-awareness and alterity: A phenomenological investigation. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. 2005. Subjectivity and selfhood: Investigating the first person perspective. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to David Lundie.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Lundie, D. Authority, Autonomy and Automation: The Irreducibility of Pedagogy to Information Transactions. Stud Philos Educ 35, 279–291 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11217-016-9517-4

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11217-016-9517-4

Keywords

Navigation