1 Introduction

Ever since Luciano Floridi re-invigorated the veridicality thesis (that [semantic] information must be true, or truthful), the discussion of this issue has been expanding (see Floridi 2004, 2005; cf. Fetzer 2004; Dodig-Crnkovic 2005). Although Floridi claims that various critical comments have “been proved unjustified, and as a result, there is now a growing consensus” about his approach (Floridi 2012, p. 432, footnotes removed),Footnote 1 the discussion has continued. Recently, I argued that Floridi’s proposed definitions suffer from counter-examples such that the sentence x is information if, and only if, x is not information (see Lundgren 2015a). The same idea was later developed and expanded by Macaulay Ferguson (2015), who furthermore argues that the choice of the definition of semantic information (between a veridical and an alethically neutral conception) is a dilemma because it is a choice between two paradoxes: information liar paradoxes and the Bar-Hillel Carnap paradox (BCP); both will be explained in this paper. This dilemma will serve as part of the dialectics of this essay.

The main aim of this essay is to argue for an alethically neutral conception of semantic information. This argument will be made by presenting counter-arguments against Floridi’s main arguments for the veridicality thesis, as well as showing that a veridical conception of semantic information leads to a contradiction. I consider Floridi’s arguments because he is currently the most influential proponent of the veridicality thesis and of a semantic conception of information. The main contribution of this essay is that an alethically neutral conception of semantic information can avoid the BCP, thus resolving the supposed dilemma between alethically neutral and veridical conceptions of semantic information. This is done by introducing a distinction between the property of being information and the property of being informative. Overall, combined with the other arguments, this speaks in favor of an alethically neutral conception of semantic information and against the veridicality thesis.

However, a preference for an alethically neutral conception over a veridical conception of semantic information does not mean that we cannot, or should not, retain the latter concept. I conclude that we should retain it as a subconcept of the former concept, i.e., as veridical semantic information.

The rest of the essay is structured as follows. I present the relevant background in Sect. 2. Then I present one conceptual problem for the veridicality thesis in Sect. 3. In Sect. 4, I present Floridi’s first argument for the veridicality thesis and arguments against it. Finally, I end by explaining and resolving the BCP, and the dilemma, as well as the other main parts of Floridi’s ‘semantic argument’ in Sect. 5. Before ending, I summarize my conclusions in Sect. 6. After the conclusions, an “Appendix” includes further discussion of the topic in Sect. 3.

Although the dialectic structure of this article is centered on Floridi’s arguments, the arguments are not aimed only at his arguments but at a broader argumentation that he exemplifies.

In the remainder of this essay, I sometimes use ‘semantic information’ instead of a ‘semantic conception of information’, and on occasion (when what is intended is clearly indicated by the context), I also simply use ‘information’ for ‘semantic information’. On occasion, I also use VT as an abbreviation for ‘the veridicality thesis’ and AN for ‘an alethically neutral conception of semantic information’.

2 Background and specification

The notion of semantic information was originally introduced by Bar-Hillel and Carnap (1964[1952], cf. Bar-Hillel and Carnap 1953), and it is part of a larger context of theories of information (see Adriaans 2013 for a brief overview). Bar-Hillel and Carnap created their approach in response to contemporary theories of information, namely, the ‘Mathematical Theory of Communication’, or ‘Theory of (Transmission of) Information’, which—according to Bar-Hillel and Carnap—“authoritative presentations” have taken “great care [...] to point out that this theory is not interested in the semantic aspects of communication” (Bar-Hillel and Carnap 1964, p. 222). Bar-Hillel and Carnap refer to two representative sources for this position: C. E. Shannon, for whom semantics issues were considered “irrelevant to the engineering problem” (Shannon quoted in ibid), and E. Colin Cherry, who thought that “semantics lies outside the scope of mathematical information theory” (Colin Cherry quoted in ibid). Bar-Hillel and Carnap focused mainly on measurements of informativity (i.e., how informative some information is).

After Bar-Hillel and Carnap, and before Floridi re-invigorated the debate on the veridicality thesis, Dretske (1981) argued, while recognizing that information “may be a semantic concept” (p. 42) that “information embodied in a signal (linguistic or otherwise) is only incidentally related to the meaning (if any) of that signal” (p. 44), and that:

[S]ignals may have a meaning but they carry information. What information a signal carries is what it is capable of “telling” us, telling us truly [...] information is that commodity capable of yielding knowledge, and [...] [i]f everything I say to you is false, then I have given you no information. (ibid)

Tellingly, he focused his analysis of information on informativity or the “amount of information” (ibid). Concerning the veridicality thesis, he famously exemplified his position by comparing “false information and mis-information” with “decoy ducks and rubber ducks” (ibid, p. 45).

Fox (1983, p. 193) took another position in relation to the verdicality thesis, arguing that information can be true or false, while misinformation is always false. His conceptual analysis focused on the relation between x informs y that p and information, and x misinforms y that p and misinformation, arguing that x informs y that p if x tells y that p and x is in a position to know that p, and x misinforms y that p if x informs y that p and p is false (ibid, p. 184).

Grice in Studies in the Way of Words stated that false information “is just not information” (1989, p. 371). Barwise and Seligman (1997) developed their account mainly based on Dretske (1981) and thus in line with his view on veridicality. Graham (1999) took a position in favor of the veridicality thesis. His conceptual analysis of information can be summed up by his claim that “in normal speech ‘information’ is an epistemologically normative term: to be newly possessed of information implies that we now know something we did not know before” (p. 89).

When Floridi re-uses the concept of ‘semantic information’, he focuses on an epistemic sense of the concept.Footnote 2 He states that he “will analyse only one crucial aspect of a specific kind of information, namely the alethic nature of declarative, semantic information, the kind of information that we normally take to be essential for epistemic purposes” (Floridi 2011, p. 82). Let us call this Floridi’s ‘characterization’ of semantic information. Although this is certainly a specific kind of information worthy of philosophical consideration, it is prima facie an open question if there is a special kind of information that is essential for epistemic purposes, and if so, how it should be defined. I will concern myself with the latter question, i.e., which conception of semantic information—alethically neutral or veridical—fits best with Floridi’s characterization of the concept of semantic information as information which is declarative, semantic, and essential for epistemic purposes.Footnote 3

Floridi (2011) identifies the basic components of semantic information as dataFootnote 4\(+\)meaning.Footnote 5 From this, he extrapolates a more rigid definition:

GDI\(\sigma \) (an infon) is an instance of semantic information if and only if:

      GDI.1 \(\sigma \) consists of n data (d), for \(n \quad \ge \) 1;

      GDI.2 the data are well-formed (wfd);

      GDI.3 the wfd are meaningful (mwfd = \(\delta )\). (Floridi 2011, p. 84)Footnote 6

There are some potential problems with GDI, but I will not concern myself with them here.Footnote 7 Instead, I focus on one particular quality of semantic information that follows from accepting GDI: the alethic neutrality of semantic information. This is what Floridi questions. He wants to add a fourth criterion to GDI, namely, that meaningful well-formed data also is truthful:

GDI*\(\sigma \) is an instance of semantic information if and only if:

      GDI*.1 \(\sigma \) consists of n data (d), for \(n \quad \ge \) 1;

      GDI*.2 the data are well-formed (wfd);

      GDI*.3 the wfd are meaningful (mwfd = \(\delta )\);

      GDI*.4 the \(\delta \) are truthful (Floridi 2011, p. 104, I have re-named the criteria           from 1.-4. to GDI*.1-GDI*.4).

Floridi uses the term ‘truthful’, rather than true, since, e.g., maps are truthful, but perhaps not true (Floridi 2011, p. 105).

The choice between these two definitions (GDI* or GDI) is not purely technical. We have a conceptual interest in understanding the nature of semantical information, e.g., as a part of our communications. It is in particular as such a concept that an alethically neutral—contrary to a veridical—definition of semantic information (such as GDI) is compatible with our commonsense uses of information. For example, as Pieter Adriaans notes, people tend to accept “If I get the information that p then I know that p” and “Secret services sometimes distribute false information” (Adriaans 2013). What Adriaans’ examples show is that the veridical nature of information is ambiguous, which is something that a neutral conception of semantic information can satisfy. These examples illustrate the kind of semantic conception of information that I intend to show can survive Floridi’s critique.

3 A liar paradox for a veridical conception of semantic information

In this part, I present one basic conceptual problem for a veridical conception of semantic information. Consider a sentence such as (1):

(1) This is not semantic information.

Suppose, which is arguably sensible, that (1) fulfills all necessary and sufficient criteria for semantic information, with the possible exception of (if it is a criterion) veridicality.Footnote 8 Now, if (1) is also true, then (1) fulfills all the criteria of a veridical conception of semantic information and is, accordingly, semantic information, but if (1) is true, then it is also true that (1) isnot semantic information. On the other hand, if (1) is false, then (1) does not fulfill all the criteria of a veridical conception of semantic information, and is not, accordingly, semantic information, but if (1) is false, then it is false that (1) is not semantic information, and consequentially, it is true that (1) is semantic information. Therefore, according to a veridical conception of semantic information, (1) is semantic information if, and only if, (1) is not semantic information. I call this the information liar paradox (and sentence 1 is an information liar sentence). It is important to note that the contradiction is a consequence of a veridicality criterion such as GDI*.4 (under the presumption of, e.g., classical logic), and it is a problem for a veridical conception of semantic information irrespective of any potential solutions to the liar paradox as such (cf. Lundgren (2015a), cf. also Macaulay Ferguson (2015) for a later similar argument).

Proponents of VT have various possible response strategies. I respond to the most plausible strategies in the “Appendix”. I argue that even if some response strategies are successful (it is not clear that they are) none will succeed without a cost. Thus, although this argument does not ultimately defeat VT, it is a strong counter-argument that needs to be dealt with.

Let us turn from paradoxical consequences from acceptance of the veridicality thesis to Floridi’s first pro-argument for the veridicality thesis and GDI*: the splitting test.

4 Is false information genuine information?

Floridi (2005) presents two main arguments in favor of GDI* over GDI. The first, which I will present below (in Sect. 4.1), is a test (the ‘splitting test’) that is intended to show that false information is not information, which is false, but rather not any kind of information at all. Next, in Sect. 4.2, I argue that the splitting test fails to establish the thesis that false information is not (semantic) information.

4.1 The ‘splitting test’

The ‘splitting test’ is based on the Geachian distinction between an attributive adjective and a predicative adjective. The argument is that ‘false’ in ‘false information’ is used as an attributive adjective rather than a predicative adjective. Floridi illustrates this distinction with ‘male constable’ and ‘good constable’. In the former, ‘male’ is a predicative adjective; for a male constable is a “person who is both male and employed as a policeman”. In the latter example, we cannot analyze the adjective in terms of a good person who is also employed as a policeman, because ‘good’ is used as an attributive adjective. Whether an adjective is predicative or attributive can vary with the context (Floridi 2011, p. 97).

Furthermore, we can use attributive adjectives in either a positive or negative way. If used positively, the “adjectives further qualify their reference x as y”, e.g., ‘good constable’, while if used negatively, the adjective negates “one or more of the qualities necessary for x to be x”. According to Floridi, the negative use is “logically equivalent to ‘not”’. An example is ‘false constable’, in which false indicates that he or she is not a constable at all. Other suggested examples are ‘forged banknote’, ‘counterfeit signature’, and ‘false alarm’ (Floridi 2011, p. 97).

Now, it is suggested that when it comes to false information—i.e., false semantic information—the use of ‘false’ is negatively attributive:

When we say that p, e.g., ‘the earth has two moons’, is false, we are using ‘false’ predicatively. The test is that the compound can be split into ‘p is a proposition’ and ‘p is a contingent falsehood’ without any semantic loss or confusion. On the contrary, when we describe p as false information, we are using ‘false’ attributively, to negate the fact that p qualifies as information at all. Why? Because ‘false information’ does not pass the test. As in the case of the false constable, the compound cannot be correctly split. It is not the case, and hence it would be a mistake or an act of misinformation to assert, that p constitutes information about the number of natural satellites orbiting around the earth and is also a falsehood. Compare this case to the one in which we qualify \(\sigma \) as digital information, which obviously splits into ‘\(\sigma \) is information’ and ‘\(\sigma \) is digital’. If false information were a genuine type of information it should pass the splitting test. It does not, so it is not. (Floridi 2011, pp. 97–98).

4.2 Against the splitting test

The splitting test may seem methodologically sound, in the sense that if no instances of semantic information pass the splitting test, then that would be a pro-argument for GDI*. However, as Scarantino and Piccinini (2010) argue, the test rests on accepting “the brute intuition that that the earth has two moons is not information. The content of this intuition is nothing but an instance of the general thesis to be established. Thus the argument is question-begging” (p. 321).

The problem, however, is even more severe because the splitting test does not seem to yield the general conclusion that a proponent of VT would desire. As previously noted, Floridi presents several examples of a negatively attributive use of ‘false’. Among these examples, the example ‘false alarm’ seems questionable; for a false alarm is still an alarm. The response to the question “did the alarm go off?” is truly “yes” although it was a false alarm (e.g., a fire alarm gets triggered even though there is no fire). Arguably, a false signature is also still a signature (we could not blame someone for having falsified a signature if he or she had provided no signature at all).Footnote 9 Thus, what we should conclude is that the principle on which the splitting test rests does not hold with generality; the examples are ambiguous.

However, it may be argued that even though the examples fail, the test still works for false (semantic) information. Take the example of a witness who gives testimony. Testimony is prima facie semantic information. However, witnesses can lie. Just because a witness lies we would not say that her testimony was not information; rather, we would say that the testimony/information she gave was false (using false in a predicative sense). To support this intuition, think of a situation in which we have two contradictory testimonies. According to a veridical conception of semantic information, a correct description of what the jury must do is to evaluate which of these testimonies is semantic information and which is not. However, this seems contrary to the standard understanding of the concept of information. Furthermore, it seems to be quite counterintuitive: Why should we have to suspend our judgment of whether something is information until we know what is true? Thus, it seems clear that the jury could, would, and should conclude that both testimonies constitute semantic information but that one of these testimonies is false and the other one is true.

The testimony example shows that the use of the concept of information—in colloquial language—tends to vary a lot. As previously mentioned, people tend to accept “If I get the information that p then I know that p” and “Secret services sometimes distribute false information”. According to Adriaans (2013), “these inconsistencies do not seem to create great trouble and in general it is clear from the pragmatic context what type of information is designated”. It seems clear that when secret services distribute false information their aim is that it should be the kind of information that is essential for epistemic purposes—and clearly, on occasion, they succeed. Because of the ambiguous nature of the concept of information, it seems that the splitting test does not work; in some contexts, it is clear that by ‘information’ we mean true information, while in other contexts ‘information’ could be used to indicate false information, overall supporting an alethically neutral conception of information.Footnote 10

It is also worth noting that if we are interested in the kind of information that is essential for epistemic purposes then empirical research shows at the very least “that exposure to negative political information continues to shape attitudes even after the information has been effectively discredited” (Thorson 2016, p. 460). This shows that the role of ‘false information’ is highly relevant if we are interested in epistemic issues and that the role of misinformation is, perhaps, not as clear-cut as we philosophers may want it to be.Footnote 11

Let me expand on a few examples that support intuitions contrary to the veridicality thesis and that show, more broadly, that the splitting test does not work. Take, for example, weather forecasts: Is a weather forecast semantic information? Intuitively, this would be a characteristic example of semantic information. But in accordance with the veridicality thesis, we would have to wait and see how reality turns out before we know if we can classify the weather forecast as information.Footnote 12 However, it seems obvious that weather forecasts pass the splitting test. If the weather forecast for tomorrow is that it will be partly sunny and raining three to five millimeters, then it seems intuitive to classify this forecast as semantic information irrespective of how the weather actually turns out. The problem for the splitting test is that our judgment of whether something is information comes before, or at least is separate from, the judgment whether that something is true (truthful) or false. We could imagine examples that are much more extreme, say predictions about the future of the universe 10 million years from now. However, predictions are particularly complicated; therefore, let us turn to other examples.Footnote 13

There are many examples of predictions, statements, and propositions that intuitively seem to be semantic information and would survive the splitting test. Proponents of the veridicality thesis would have to say that Einstein showed that Newton’s mechanics is not semantic information. But it is much more reasonable to think that we can classify Newton’s mechanics as semantic information and add that it is false. Now, we should note that GDI*.4 actually requires truthfulness, not truth, which may seem to lessen the force of this critique. Maps are strictly false (as their projections presume a flat earth) but still truthful (enough). Likewise, so are Newton’s theories—for most applications. However, such a conception of veridical semantic information is, in fact, less convincing. The problem is that what is semantic information would be contextually relative, so while Newton’s mechanics would be semantic information in some contexts, it would not be that in other contexts. This is a highly confusing conception of semantic information.Footnote 14 It seems much more sensible to say that Newton’s theories are semantic information, information which is strictly not true (but for most purposes sufficiently close to the truth).

Let us turn to Floridi’s ‘semantic argument’, and the final argument for an alethically neutral conception of semantic information.

5 Must information be informative?

Floridi’s second (2005) argument against a neutral conception of semantic information was merely a sketch at that time, which he developed in Floridi (2007). The argument is rooted in dilemmas concerning informativity and depends partly on the BCP.

These arguments build up to the final conclusive argument in Sect. 5.2, where I show that an alethically neutral conception of semantic information can resolve the BCP, as well as other elements of the semantic argument.

5.1 BCP and the ‘semantic argument’

Floridi (2005) sketched a semantic argument in one paragraph; the following sentences supply the main locus of the argument:

If false information does not count as semantic junk but as a type of information, it becomes difficult to make sense of the ordinary phenomenon of semantic erosion. Operators like “not” lose their semantic power to corrupt information, information becomes semantically indestructible and the informative content of a repository can decrease only by physical and syntactical manipulation of data. (Floridi 2005, p. 365, cf. 2011, p. 104)

Later, in order to develop this argument, Floridi (2007) introduced ‘four principles’, which he used to argue that only contingent truths are information. In favor of these principles, Floridi (2011) claimed that “[a]ny satisfactory understanding of semantic information should implement” these principles (p. 98) and that the principles are “uncontroversial and fairly standard assumptions in information theory and in the philosophy of information” (p. 99). However, I will not address the nature of these principles in any great detail, as they are neither argued for nor logically convincing, and contrary to what is claimed, we can question whether they are standard assumptions or not.Footnote 15

What is important here is not the four principles as such, because the problem that the semantic argument formulates can be expressed without them. However, one thesis that is necessary for the formulation of this problem is the supposed necessary relation between the property of being informative and the property of being information, which I will question. This problem is exemplified by the fourth principle (P.4), according to which anything that lacks informative content is necessarily not information (ergo, the property of being informative is necessary for the property of being information). This premise is not, as seems to be supposed, obviously true; I question this premise in Sect. 5.2.

The aim of the semantic argument is the conclusion that a conception of semantic information that includes anything but contingent truths is too inclusive.Footnote 16 Two main points of the argument (of relevance for this paper) are as follows.

First, the semantic argument against contradictions (and, arguably, contingent falsehoods) is rooted in the BCP, which is the result that “a self-contradictory sentence, hence one which no ideal receiver would accept, is regarded as carrying with it the most inclusive information” (Bar-Hillel and Carnap 1964[1952], p. 229, quoted in Floridi 2011, p. 100). This result is due to the supposed inverse relation between the informative content (informativity) of some information and its probability (lower probability implies higher informativity).Footnote 17 This basic principle is easily motivated by examples; e.g., if I tell you that we have a meeting next week on Wednesday at 7 p.m., then the truth of this statement is less probable then the truth of the statement that we have a meeting next week. The former is more informative than the latter, because it excludes more alternatives. Based on Bar-Hillel and Carnap’s principles (that the informativity of some information is inversely related to its probability) and under the presumption that all information is informative (which Bar-Hillel and Carnap also presume), it can be concluded that:

Since contradictions are most unlikely, to the point of having zero probability, they are very informative; indeed they are the most informative propositions. (Floridi 2011, p. 100)

The problem is that we rarely take a false statement as very informative, perhaps not informative at all. Proponents of the veridicality thesis have argued that this problem requires a restriction of semantic information which excludes contradictions (Floridi 2011, pp. 100–101; cf. Primiero 2007, p. 406).Footnote 18 The BCP is a problem that an alethically neutral conception of semantic information needs to deal with; I do so in Sect. 5.2.

Second, the semantic argument for the exclusion of contingent falsehoods focuses on the following example: If we accept contingently false information as information, then the informative content of ‘Sextus Empiricus died in ad [sic] 201, when Simplicius went to Rome’ and ‘Sextus Empiricus was alive in ad [sic] 201, when Simplicius went to Alexandria’ would be the same. However, “[q]uantitatively, this may be true, but semantically it seems unacceptable. The former would count as information, if true; the latter would not, if false” (Floridi 2011, p. 103). The idea here must be that both sentences are equally probable (given the available information) and therefore, are quantitatively the same. This idea is basically an example of the core of the semantic argument: If false information is information, then “[o]perators like ‘not’ lose their semantic power to corrupt information” (Floridi 2011, p. 104, cf. quote above). It should be noted, again, that it is evident that the semantic argument takes informativity to be a necessary property for information, which follows from the core of the argument and is directly evident in some of the four principles (such as P.4).

Let us turn to the resolution of these problems.

5.2 Disentangling informativeness and information

In this section, I address the importance of distinguishing between what information is from how informative some information is. I do this in order to resolve the BCP (and the rest of the semantic argument), and thus, add to the arguments for an alethically neutral conception of semantic information. However, although my conclusion (which follows from my solution to the BCP and the examples provided in Sect. 4.2) is in favor of an alethically neutral conception of semantic information, I also argue that veridical semantic information is still a meaningful and important subconcept of semantic information.

At the core of the semantic argument is the principle that semantic information is necessarily informative. Let us restrict ourselves to that claim. Although it may seem as if the prima facie intuition is on the side of proponents of VT, it is clearly not true on closer analysis.Footnote 19

One may consider some of the examples from Sect. 4.2 directed against the splitting test. If I am right then, e.g., the false statement of a witness constitutes semantic information. Thus, if we follow Floridi in accepting that a false statement is not informative (because it is false), this would be a counter-example to the conception of informativity as a necessary criterion for semantic information, rather than an example of non-information. It is sensible to think that misinformation fails to inform, irrespective of whether misinformation is information or not. If someone provides us with information, and we later find out that it was false, then we may complain, sensibly, that what they told us was not informative.Footnote 20

Now, as previously noted, there is an efficient intuition pump in the semantic argument, i.e., the BCP. The driving force behind the BCP is the idea that if we accept an alethically neutral definition of semantic information then we must accept that contradictions have maximum informational content (which supposedly is counter-intuitive). However, the consequences of the BCP also depend on the premise that all semantic information is informative. If we avoid conflating the property of being information with the property of being informative, then there is no paradox to speak of. The technical issue, which follows if we want to retain the operators used by Bar-Hillel and Carnap, can be fixed, perhaps in the way suggested by Floridi (2004, 2011, chapter 5); but the philosophical issue is resolved by realizing that there was no problem to begin with. We can have an alethically neutral definition of semantic information and, if we want, still claim that the informativity of semantic information depends on truth. Thus, we can deal with the question of informativity as a concept relating to truth without needing to accept any version of the veridicality thesis.Footnote 21 The same argument is applicable to contingently false information; i.e., that false information generally is less informative than truthful information (or not informative at all as the example of the incorrect changes in the historical accounts of Sextus Empiricus aims to show) does not mean that false information is not information. It just says something about the informativity of false information. Likewise, it is much more reasonable to think that Newton’s theories are information, but their informativeness varies with the requirements of various applications.

BCP served as part of the basis for the dilemma that Macaulay Ferguson had in mind when he argued that we have to choose between two paradoxes. On the one hand, we have the theories of Bar-Hillel and Carnap, which allow false information as semantic information and therefore suffer from the BCP, and on the other hand, we have the theories of Fred Dretske and Luciano Floridi, which suffer from counter-examples such as the information liar sentence (Macaulay Ferguson 2015). This dilemma is resolved by giving up the conflation of informativeness with (semantic) information. We can then accept some alethically neutral definition of semantic information while dealing with informativeness as a separate issue.

The core of the semantic argument was that “operators like ‘not’ lose their semantic power to corrupt information” (see Floridi 2005, p. 365, 2011, p. 104). Now, it is true that ‘not’ (when used in a meaningful sense) cannot change semantic information either into non-semantic information or into non-information. However, from this it does not follow that operators like ‘not’ lack semantic power to corrupt information, because they can still be used to make some informative semantic information non-informative (and vice versa).

Thus, disentangling the property of being information and the property of being informative resolves the semantic argument in favor of an alethically neutral conception of semantic information. Although this insight is generally compatible with various other conceptualizations of the two concepts, and informativity, in particular, a few properties follow as a corollary. The main difference between the property of being information and the property of being informative is that the latter takes on part of the properties that information supposedly has under the veridicality thesis. Under VT, whether some data are information is contingent and depends on the truth of that information, e.g., on the state of the world. In Sect. 4.2, I supply various examples that aim to show that this idea is false.Footnote 22 Thus, whether some data constitute information does not depend, e.g., on the state of the world. However, whether something is informative arguably does.Footnote 23 This is why I have argued that we ought to retain veridical semantic information as a subconcept of semantic information.

Finally, much more could be said about the properties of these concepts. However, as I wish the main insight of this article to remain as compatible with as many accounts of informativity as possible I will not make any suggestions for further qualifications of the two concepts here.

6 Conclusions

In this article, I have argued that a veridical conception of semantic information suffers from contradictions such that some sentence isinformation if, and only if, it is not information. Furthermore, I have argued against the splitting test, which aims to show that false information is not genuine information, and I have presented counter-examples against a veridical conception of semantic information. Last, based on a distinction between the property of being informative and the property of being information (supported partly based the intuition-driven arguments) I resolved some semantic arguments, such as the BCP, directed against an alethically neutral conception of semantic information, while re-introducing veridical semantic information as a subconcept of semantic information.

In summary, I hope to have shown that there are good reasons to adopt a non-veridical conception of semantic information. I also hope to have shown that veridical semantic information is still useful, as a subconcept of semantic information.