Skip to main content
Log in

Inter-affectivity and social coupling: on contextualized empathy

  • Published:
Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Recent enactive approach to social cognition stresses the indispensability of social affordance with regard to social understanding and contends that it is affordance that primarily solicits one’s reaction to the other, such that one becomes affected by the other and attends to the other’s situated appearance in the first place. What remains to be explored, however, is the sense in which social affordance is delineated by an affective sphere and the extent to which the affective sphere serves as a meaning constraint for social sense-making. In this paper, we analyze Husserl’s genetic theory of affection, so as to better understand the nature of the social affective sphere. And we argue that social understanding takes places at different levels and it is at the passive and pre-reflective level that the social surroundings are pre-delineated by a sort of affective ambience where the empathizer and the empathizee come into contact. Once this is appreciated, we can better articulate the affective structure of social affordance and its meaning constituents. And we show that, at the passive level, social coupling is in nature an affective intertwinement between oneself and the other and it consists of a particular kind of corporeal intentionality with which one adverts to the other’s presence and responds to the other’s appeal.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Bower and Gallagher (2013) and Colombetti (2017) clearly notice that Husserl’s work on affection may help to better elucidate the affective dimension of social understanding, they nonetheless merely mention him by passing and have not offered further analysis of his work.

  2. For a fuller overview of Husserl’s theory of empathy, see Zahavi (2012). As Luo (2018) demonstrates, although empathy is a quasi-perceptual experience, it is essentially different from perception of physical objects, not only because other human bodies are expressive but also because empathy is fundamentally characterized by a twofold intentionality directed at the other.

  3. Dings (2018) recently proposed a non-Husserlian account of how affordances solicit action, and he suggested that there are three factors that we need to take in account when we conceptualize the solicitation in question: valence, force and mineness. It might seem strange that he didn’t ever mention Husserl’s theory, even though some of his characterizations are fundamentally akin to Husserl’s. Nonetheless, in this paper, I focus more on the pre-reflective character of affect and the meaningfulness of the affective sphere, rather than engaging with the question of, say, “what determines whether a particular affordance solicits to act or not” (Dings 2018, p. 682), for the latter, see also Mühlhoff (2015).

  4. Zahavi (2012) distinguishes two related yet essentially different questions with regard to social cognition. It is one thing to ask whether we correctly understand another person’s mental states, and it is quite another to ask whether another person is minded at all.

  5. In this regard, Husserl is suspicious about whether sheer sensuous data, something completely isolated from the Gestalt whole, could register in perceptual experience at all (Husserl, 1970, p. 85). And he further holds that mere sensuous objects–objects deprived of any meaning and value are the results of abstraction and, thus, they can hardly touch emotion (see Lotz, 2007, p. 40; Hart, 1992, pp. 88–89; Fuchs & Koch, 2014, p. 2).

  6. Aron Gurwitsch (2010) further distinguishes the conscious field into three constitutive segments: theme, thematic field and the unthematic or marginal field. See also Bégout (2007, p. 23) for further discussions.

  7. To be sure, this sort of dyadic inter-relation should not be confused with a proper sort of “reciprocal” engagement where both the empathizer and the empathizee need to be aware of each other, because the former denotes a particular correlation between the other’s affective pull and the empathizer’s bodily advertence, wherein there is no need for the other to be aware of the empathizer. In this regard, “reciprocal” is a too much strong term to describe what is at stake. For a further discussion of inter-affectivity, see Behnke (2008).

  8. Colombetti seems to have noticed the passive aspect of affectivity, as she maintains that the surrounding world has a sort of “demand character” by which the surrounding world by itself solicits enactors to take further actions upon it. Fur a further analysis of the demand character, see Mühlhoff (2015).

  9. To be noted, Husserl makes a similar differentiation between “genuine empathy” and “ungenuine empathy.” As he writes, “ungenuine empathy is the passive associative indicating of a foreign subjectivity, whereas genuine empathy is actively co-doing and co-suffering, letting oneself be motivated egoically, but also, with respect to the underlying ground, pursuing the inner motivation instead of association” (Husserl, 1973a, p. 455). To paraphrase, genuine empathy is an active form of empathizing with others by actively making use of one’s own experiences, knowledge and intellectual capacity, so as to achieve a better understanding of others in a certain circumstance. By contrast, ungenuine empathy is a prior and passive experience of the other, without “subsequent reflection” [nachkommenden Reflexion] upon such a passive encounter.

  10. For a fuller account of feeling intentionality and the role it plays in our being in the world, see Goldie (2002), Ratcliffe (2005) and Ratcliffe (2008).

  11. As a reviewer pointed out, Husserl’s theory of feeling or feeling intentionality, as it is elaborated in Logical Investigations and Ideas I, is the view that feeling intentionality is founded upon perceptual presentation [For a further analysis of the founding relationship between feeling and perception, see, e.g., Lee (1998), Drummond (2006), Jardine (2015, 2017)]. It might follow that the sort of bodily feeling at the affective level when encountering another person depends upon perceptual presentation of the other, i.e., empathic perception (Fremdwahrnehnung), such that it is on the basis of a prior form of empathic experience of the other that social coupling can be instituted. However, we also think that Husserl’s theory of feeling or feeling intentionality in light of his genetic analysis proves to be substantially different from his earlier view, and he thinks that affective feeling is passive and pre-thematic in kind and that it genetically precedes perceptual presentation of a specific object [see, e.g., Steinbock (2004)]. Luo (2019) has explained to what extent Husserl develops his view of feeling intentionality in contrast with his earlier one in the fifth Logical Investigation.

References

  • Bégout, B. (2007). Husserl and the phenomenology of attention. In L. Boi, P. Kerszberg, & F. Patras (Eds.), Rediscovering phenomenology (pp. 13–32). Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Behnke, E. A. (2008). Interkinaesthetic affectivity: A phenomenological approach. Continental Philosophy Review, 41, 143–161.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bower, M., & Gallagher, S. (2013). Bodily affects as prenoetic elements in enactive perception. Phenomenology and Mind, 4(1), 109–131.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bruttomesso, M. C. (2016). Experiencing the other. How expressivity and value-based perception provide a non-solipsistic account of empathy. Rivista internazionale di Filosofia e Psicologia, 7(3), 350–364.

    Google Scholar 

  • Colombetti, G. (2017). Enactive affectivity, extended. Topoi, 36(3), 445–455.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Colombetti, G., & Torrance, S. (2009). Emotion and ethics: An inter-(en)active approach. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 8, 505–526.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Jaegher, H., & Paolo, D. (2007). Participatory sense-making: An enactive approach to social cognition. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 6(4), 485–507.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Di Paolo, E., Rohde, M., & De Jaegher, H. (2010). Horizons for the enactive mind: values, social interaction, and play. In J. Stewart, O. Gapenne, & E. Di Paolo (Eds.), Enaction: toward a new paradigm for cognitive science (pp. 33–87). MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dings, R. (2018). Understanding phenomenological differences in how affordances solicit action. An exploration. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 17(4), 681–699.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Drummond, J. (2006). Respect as a moral emotion: A phenomenological approach. Husserl Studies, 22(1), 1–27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fuchs, T. (2013). The phenomenology and development of social perspectives. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 12(4), 655–683.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fuchs, T., & De Jaegher, H. (2009). Enactive intersubjectivity: Participatory sense-making and mutual incorporation. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 8(4), 465–486.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fuchs, T., & Koch, S. C. (2014). Embodied affectivity: On moving and being moved. Frontiers in Psychology, 5(508), 1–12.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2004). Understanding Interpersonal Problems in Autism: Interaction Theory as An Alternative to Theory of Mind. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 11(3), 199–217.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2009). Two problems of intersubjectivity. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 16, 289–308.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2013). The socially extended mind. Cognitive Systems Research, 25–26, 4–12.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2017). Enactivist interventions: Rethinking the mind. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S., & Hutto, D. (2008). Understanding others through primary interaction and narrative practice. In J. Zlatev, T. Racine, C. Sinha, & E. Itkonen (Eds.), The shared mind: Perspectives on intersubjectivity (pp. 17–38). John Benjamins.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S., & Varga, S. (2014). Social constraints on the direct perception of emotions and intentions. Topoi, 33(1), 185–199.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gibson, J. J. (2015). The ecological approach to visual perception. Psychology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldie, P. (2002). Emotions, feelings and intentionality. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 1(3), 235–254.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gurwitsch, A. (1979). Human encounters in the social world. A. Métraux (Ed.), (F. Kersten, Trans.). Duquesne University Press.

  • Gurwitsch, A. (2010). The collected works of Aron Gurwitsch (1901–1973): volume III: The field of consciousness: theme, thematic field, and marginal consciousness. Zaner, R. & Embree, L. (Eds.), Springer.

  • Hart, J. G. (1992). The person and the common life: Studies in a Husserlian social ethics. Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1996). Being and time (J. Stambaugh, Trans.). State University of New York Press.

  • Held, K. (1972). Das Problem der Intersubjektivität und die Idee einer phänomenologischen Transzendentalphilosophie. In K. Held & U. Claesges (Eds.), Perspektiven transzendentalphänomenologischer Forschung: Für Ludwig Langdgrebe zum 70. Geburstag von seinem Kölner Schulern (pp. 3–60). Den Haag: Martinus Nijhoff.

  • Husserl, E. (1960). Cartesian meditations: An introduction to phenomenology (Dorion Cairns, Trans.). Martinus Nijhoff.

  • Husserl. E. (1962). Phänomenologische psychologie. Vorlesungen sommersemester 1925. W. Biemel (Ed.). Martinus Nijhoff

  • Husserl, E. (1970). The crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology: An introduction to phenomenological philosophy (David Carr, Trans.). Northwestern University Press.

  • Husserl, E. (1973a). Zur Phänomenologie der Intersubjektivität. Texte aus dem Nachlass. Erster Teil: 1905–1920. Iso Kern (Ed.). Martinus Nijhoff

  • Husserl, E. (1973b). Zur Phänomenologie der Intersubjektivität. Texte aus dem Nachlass. Zweiter Teil: 1921–1928. Iso Kern (Ed.). Martinus Nijhoff

  • Husserl, E. (1973c). Zur Phänomenologie der Intersubjektivität. Texte aus dem Nachlass. Dritter Teil: 1929–1935. Iso Kern (Ed.). Martinus Nijhoff

  • Husserl, E. (1989). Ideas pertaining to a pure phenomenology and to a phenomenological philosophy. Second book. Studies in the phenomenology of constitution (Richard Rojcewicz & Andre Schuwer, Trans.). Kluwer Academic Publishers.

  • Husserl, E. (2001). Analyses concerning passive and active synthesis. Lectures on transcendental logic (Anthony J. Steinbock, Trans.). Kluwer Academic Publishers

  • Jardine, J. (2015). Stein and Honneth on empathy and emotional recognition. Human Studies, 38, 567–589.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jardine, J. (2017). Elementary recognition and empathy: A Husserlian account. Metodo, 5(1), 143–170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kiverstein, J. (2015). Empathy and the responsiveness to social affordances. Consciousness and Cognition, 36, 532–542.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lee, N.-I. (1998). Edmund Husserl’s phenomenology of mood. In D. Zahavi & N. Natalie (Eds.), Alterity and facticity: New perspectives on Husserl (pp. 103–120). Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lotz, C. (2007). From affectivity to subjectivity: Husserl’s phenomenology revisited. Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Luo, Z. (2018). Seeing-in and twofold empathic intentionality: A Husserlian account. Continental Philosophy Review, 51(4), 301–321.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Luo, Z. (2019). Affection, body and feeling intentionality. Monthly Review of Philosophy and Culture, 547, 117–134.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (1998). Criteria, defeasibility, and knowledge. In J. McDowell, Meaning, knowledge, and reality (pp. 369–394). Harvard University Press.

  • Mishara, A. (1990). Husserl and Freud: Time, memory and the unconscious. Husserl Studies, 7(1), 29–58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mühlhoff, R. (2015). Affective resonance and social interaction. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 14(4), 1001–1019.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ratcliffe, M. (2005). The feeling of being. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 12(8–9), 43–60.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ratcliffe, M. (2008). Feelings of being: Phenomenology, psychiatry and the sense of reality. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ratcliffe, M. J. (2017). Empathy without simulation. In M. Summa, T. Fuchs, & L. Vanzago (Eds.), Imagination and social perspectives: Approaches from phenomenology and psychopathology (pp. 199–220). Routledge.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Sartre, J. P. (2003). Being and Nothingness (H. E. Barnes, Trans.). Routledge.

  • Stein, E. (2008). Zum Problem der Einfühlung (Vol. 5). Herder.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steinbock, A. (2004). Affection and attention: On phenomenological of becoming aware. Continental Philosophy Review, 37, 21–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stueber, K. (2006). Rediscovering empathy: Agency, folk psychology and the human sciences. The MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Waldenfels, B. (2007). The question of the other. The Chinese University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Waldenfels, B. (2010). Attention suscitée et dirigée (English version: Phenomenology of attention). Alter, 18, 33–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2007). Expression and empathy. In D. D. Hutto & M. Ratcliffe (Eds.), Folk psychology re-assessed. Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2011). Empathy and direct social perception: A phenomenological proposal. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 2(3), 541–558.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2012). Empathy and mirroring: Husserl and Gallese. In R. Brenet & U. Melle (Eds.), Life, subjectivity & art (pp. 217–254). Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2014). Empathy and other-directed intentionality. Topoi, 33(1), 129–142.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

This paper is supported by Guangdong Provincial Fund of Social Sciences and Humanities (No. GD18YZX01). We’d like to sincerely thank two anonymous reviewers for their useful comments and suggestions, and in particular to reviewer No. 2, whose linguistic advices and continuous insistence on further revisions have immensely helped to improve the paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Zhida Luo.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Xiaowei Gui is co-first author of the article

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Luo, Z., Gui, X. Inter-affectivity and social coupling: on contextualized empathy. Phenom Cogn Sci 21, 377–393 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-021-09778-3

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-021-09778-3

Keywords

Navigation