Skip to main content
Log in

Rational beliefs in rationalizability

  • Published:
Theory and Decision Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper I scrutinize the “rational beliefs” in the concept of rationalizability in strategic games [Bernheim (Econometrica 52:1007–1028, 1984), Pearce (Econometrica 52:1029–1051, 1984)]. I illustrate through an example that a rationalizable strategy may not be supported by a “rational belief”, at least under one plausible interpretation of “rational belief”. I offer an alternative formulation of “rational belief” in the concept of rationalizability, which yields a novel epistemic interpretation of the notion of point-rationalizability.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. In an interesting paper, Kline (2013) demonstrated how to evaluate the famous Muddy Children Puzzle by using “rational” beliefs.

  2. The notion of rationalizability captures the strategic implications of the assumption of “common knowledge of rationality” [see Tan and Werlang (1988)], which is different from the assumption of “commonality of beliefs” or “correct conjectures” in an equilibrium [see Aumann and Brandenburger (1995)].

  3. The set of player i’s mixed strategies is a probability space on a finite set of pure strategies, which can be viewed as a simplex in a finite-dimensional Euclidean space.

  4. Believing the truth is, certainly, intrinsically valuable. We intrinsically want to have true beliefs. Also, our original interest in the truth has an instrumental basis too. Generally speaking, believing the truth serves us better than falsehoods and better than no beliefs at all in coping with adverse uncertainties. To be sure, maximizing expected utility is not the epistemic goal for the rationality of belief. To achieve Bayesian rationality in a strategic context, we simply want the players’ beliefs to be epistemically rational. See Foley (1987), Moser et al. (1998), and Nozick (1993) for extensive discussions.

  5. It is worth noting that, in these cases, this sort of “rational beliefs” also gives rise to some doubt about the appropriateness of the formalism of “rational belief”. According to BP-formula, never is there such a unique “rational belief” unless the state space is a singleton.

  6. A strategy profile x is point-rationalizable if there is a subset Y of \(\ X\) such that (i) \(x\in Y\) and (ii) \(\forall i\in N\), \(\forall y_{i}\in Y_{i}\), \(\exists y_{-i}\in Y_{-i}\) such that \(y_{i}\in \mathop {\mathrm{argmax}}\nolimits _{z_{i}\in X_{i}}U_{i}\left( z_{i},y_{-i}\right) \). Let \(R^{*}\) be the set of all the point-rationalizable strategy profiles. Then, \(R^{*}\) is a largest (w.r.t. set inclusion) set satisfying (ii) and, moreover, \(R^{*}\) can be derived by the iterated elimination of never-best response with respect to “point-beliefs” [see Bernheim (1984, Proposition 3.1)].

References

  • Aumann, R. J. (1976). Agreeing to disagree. Annals of Statistics, 4, 1236–1239.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aumann, R. J. (1995). Backward induction and common knowledge of rationality. Games and Economic Behavior, 8, 6–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aumann, R. J., & Brandenburger, A. (1995). Epistemic conditions for Nash equilibrium. Econometrica, 63, 1161–1180.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Battigalli, P., & Bonanno, G. (1999). Recent results on belief, knowledge and the epistemic foundations of game theory. Research in Economics, 53, 149–225.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bonanno, G., & Nehring, K. (1994). On Stalnaker’s notion of strong rationalizability and Nash equilibrium in perfect information games. Theory and Decision, 45, 291–295.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bernheim, B. D. (1984). Rationalizable strategic behavior. Econometrica, 52, 1007–1028.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dekel, E., & Gul, F. (1997). Rationality and knowledge in game theory. In D. Kreps & K. Wallis (Eds.), Advances in economics and econometrics: theory and applications. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foley, R. (1987). The theory of epistemic rationality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

  • Gilboa, I., Postlewaite, A., & Schmeidler, D. (2012). Rationality of belief. Synthese, 187, 11–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harsanyi, J. C. (1982). Subjective probability and the theory of games: comments on Kadane and Larkey’s paper. Management Science, 28, 120–124.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kadane, J. B., & Larkey, P. D. (1982). Subjective probability and the theory of games. Management Science, 28, 113–120.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kline, J. J. (2013). Evaluations of epistemic components for resolving the muddy children puzzle. Economic Theory, 53, 61–83.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lucas, R. E. (1972). Expectations and the neutrality of money. Journal of Economic Theory, 4, 103–124.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Milgrom, P., & Stokey, N. (1982). Information, trade and common knowledge. Journal of Economic Theory, 26, 17–27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moser, P. K., Mulder, D. H., & Trout, J. D. (1998). The theory of knowledge: a thematic approach. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Muth, J. F. (1961). Rational expectations and the theory of price movements. Econometrica, 29, 315–335.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nozick, R. (1993). The nature of rationality. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

  • Osborne, M. J., & Rubinstein, A. (1994). A course in game theory. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

  • Pearce, D. G. (1984). Rationalizable strategic behavior and the problem of perfection. Econometrica, 52, 1029–1051.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Savage, L. (1954). The foundations of statistics. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R. (1994). On the evaluation of solution concepts. Theory and Decision, 37, 49–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tan, T., & Werlang, S. (1988). The Bayesian foundations of solution concepts of games. Journal of Economic Theory, 45, 370–391.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Xiao Luo.

Additional information

I am grateful to Yossi Greenberg for his encouragement and valuable comments. Financial support from National University of Singapore is gratefully acknowledged.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Luo, X. Rational beliefs in rationalizability. Theory Decis 81, 189–198 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11238-015-9528-6

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11238-015-9528-6

Keywords

Navigation