Skip to main content
Log in

Empiricism and Intelligent Design I: Three Empiricist Challenges

  • Original Article
  • Published:
Erkenntnis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Due to the logical relations between theism and intelligent design (id), there are two challenges to theism that also apply to id. In the falsifiability challenge, it is charged that theism is compatible with every observation statement and thus asserts nothing. I argue that the contentious assumptions of this challenge can be avoided without loss of precision by charging theism (and thus id) directly with the lack of observational assertions. In the translatability challenge, it is charged that theism can be translated into a (non-theistic) set of observation statements without loss of cognitive content. I argue that the contentious assumptions of this challenge are avoided by the related charge that the (non-theistic) evolutionary theory makes all the observational assertions of id, while the converse does not hold. Elliott Sober has argued that id meets the falsifiability challenge, but, since it makes almost no observational assertions, is not testable. I point out two problems with Sober’s argument and show that id is both deductively and probabilistically testable. Sober’s argument, I suggest, inconsistently combines the modified falsifiability challenge with the modified translatability challenge. If his claims about id’s observational assertions are true, however, id succumbs to the modified translatability challenge.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. With a reference to his discussion of the trinity, Swinburne adds in a footnote: “In understanding God as a person, while being fair to the Judaic and Islamic view of God, I am oversimplifying the Christian view.”

  2. Nielsen (1966, 13) lists further definitions according to which God is a designer.

  3. Mackie (1982, ch. 12 and p. 230) gives a critical discussion of such approaches.

  4. Accordingly, Flew’s challenge is a question about the personal beliefs of his fellow disputants, and the goal is to elucidate what assertions the theistic statements make according to them, and thus what the words ‘create’ and ‘love’ mean according to them when it comes to God.

  5. I owe this example to an anonymous referee.

  6. Since Sober does not use ‘prediction’ only to refer to claims about the future, I take it to be synonymous with ‘assertion’.

  7. This argument can be made more precise and much longer (Lutz 2012, claim 8.7).

  8. As with the falsifiability challenge, Tooley (1975, 505–506) uses an intentionally underspecified notion of testability to account for probabilistic inferences. And as in the case of the falsifiability challenge, this confuses the indicator of a property (being tested by the same observation statements) with the property itself (making the same observational assertions).

  9. The claim by many id proponents that et has been disconfirmed is critically discussed by, for example, Sober (2008, §2.6), Elsberry and Shallit (2011), and Häggström (2007a, b), and in this article’s companion piece (Lutz 2011, §5).

  10. This argument can also be made more precise and much longer (Lutz 2012, claim 9.2).

  11. It is also easily shown that two theories are empirically equivalent if and only if each theory makes all the observational assertions of the other (Lutz 2012, claim 8.3).

  12. Sober never spells out precisely which observational assertions id makes besides adap.

  13. This assumes that adap does not contain all probabilistic assertions of et. This is clearly what Sober assumes, for otherwise id would make all probabilistic empirical assertions of et, and thus it would hold that et “doesn’t predict much of anything”.

  14. There are also more general problems with contrastive testability, independently of id (Lutz 2012, §8.3).

References

  • Ayer, A. J. (1936). Language, truth and logic. London: Victor Gollanz. 1st edition. References are to the second edition (Ayer 1946).

  • Ayer, A. J. (1946). Language, truth and logic, 2nd edn. London: Victor Gollanz.

    Google Scholar 

  • Braithwaite, R. B. (1955). An Empiricist’s view of the nature of religious belief. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. The ninth Arthur Stanley Eddington Memorial Lecture. References are to the reprint (Diamond and Litzenburg 1975, 127–147).

  • Byrne, J. M. (2004). Bultmann and Tillich. In G. Jones (ed.), The Blackwell companion to modern theology, Blackwell companions to religion (pp. 372–387). Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishing.

  • Diamond, M. L. (1975a). The challenge of contemporary empiricism. In Diamond and Litzenburg (1975), pp. 3–62.

  • Diamond, M. L. (1975b). Verificationism: Difficulties and proposals. In Diamond and Litzenburg (1975), pp. 435–445.

  • Diamond, M. L., & Litzenburg, T. V., (eds.) (1975). The logic of God: Theology and verification. Indianapolis, IN: Bobbs-Merill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elsberry, W., & Shallit, J. (2011). Information theory, evolutionary computation, and Dembski’s “complex specified information”. Synthese, 178(2):237–270. Special issue: Evolution and its Rivals, edited by Glenn Branch and James H. Fetzer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flew, A. (1950). Theology and falsification. University, 1:1–8. References are to the reprint (Diamond and Litzenburg 1975, 257–259).

  • Flew, A. (1975). “Theology and falsification” in retrospect. In Diamond and Litzenburg (1975), pp. 269–283.

  • Häggström, O. (2007a). Intelligent Design and the nfl theorems. Biology and Philosophy, 22(2), 217–230.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Häggström, O. (2007b). Uniform distribution is a model assumption. http://www.math.chalmers.se/~olleh/reply_to_Dembski.pdf. Archived at http://www.webcitation.org/5tsNDuhBm.

  • Hansson, S. O. (2008). Science and pseudo-science. In: E. N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. The Metaphysics Research Lab, Center for the Study of Language and Information, Stanford University, Stanford, fall 2008 edition.

  • Harsanyi, J. C. (1975). Can the maximin principle serve as a basis for morality? A critique of John Rawls’s theory. The American Political Science Review, 69(2), 594–606.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hartwig, M. D., & Meyer, S. C. (1993). A note to teachers. In: P. Davis, D. H. Kenyon, Of pandas and people: The central question of biological origins (2nd edn., pp. 153–164). Richardson, TX: Foundation for Thought and Ethics.

  • Hempel, C. G. (1965). The theoretician’s dilemma. In Aspects of scientific explanation and other essays in the philosophy of science (pp. 173–226). New York: The Free Press.

  • Laudan, L. (1982). Commentary: Science at the bar—causes for concern. Science, Technology, & Human Values, 7(41), 16–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, L. (1983). More on creationism. Science, Technology, & Human Values, 8(1), 36–38.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lutz, S. (2011). Empiricism and Intelligent Design II: Analyzing Intelligent Design. Erkenntnis.

  • Lutz, S. (2012). Criteria of empirical significance: Foundations, relations, applications. PhD thesis, Utrecht University. http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/id/eprint/9117.

  • Mackie, J. L. (1982). The miracle of theism. Arguments for and against the existence of God. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthews, G. B. (1964). Theology and natural theology. The Journal of Philosophy, 61(3), 99–108.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nielsen, K. (1966). On fixing the reference range of ‘God’. Religious Studies, 2(1), 13–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Niiniluoto, I. (1972). Inductive systematization: Definition and a critical survey. Synthese, 25(1–2).

  • Paley, W. (1802). Natural theology: Or, evidences of the existence and attributes of the deity. Collected from the appearances of nature. London: R. Foulder. References are to the reprint (Paley 1830).

  • Paley, W. (1830). Natural theology: Or, evidences of the existence and attributes of the deity. Collected from the appearances of nature. Cambridge: Hilliard and Brown.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rothbart, D. (1982). Demarcating genuine science from pseudoscience. In: P. Grim (ed.), Philosophy of science and the occult, SUNY Series in Philosophy. Albany: State University of New York Press.

  • Sobel, J. H. (2004). Logic and theism. Arguments for and against beliefs in God. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. (1990). Contrastive empiricism. In: C. W. Savage (ed.), Scientific theories, volume 14 of Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science (pp. 392–410). Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.

  • Sober, E. (1999). Testability. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 73(2), 47–76.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. (2007). What is wrong with Intelligent Design? The Quarterly Review of Biology, 82(1), 3–8.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. (2008). Evidence and evolution: The logic behind the science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Swinburne, R. (2004). The existence of God, 2nd edn. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tooley, M. (1975). Theological statements and the question of an empiricist criterion of cognitive significance. In Diamond and Litzenburg (1975) pp. 481–524.

  • Tuomela, R. (1973). Theoretical concepts. Number 10 in the library of exact philosophy. Wien: Springer.

Download references

Acknowledgments

Many thanks to Thomas Müller and Elliott Sober for helpful discussions and two anonymous referees for trenchant and exceptionally gracious comments.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Sebastian Lutz.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Lutz, S. Empiricism and Intelligent Design I: Three Empiricist Challenges. Erkenn 78, 665–679 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-012-9391-6

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-012-9391-6

Keywords

Navigation