Skip to main content
Log in

How to Compare Homology Concepts: Class Reasoning About Evolution and Morphology in Phylogenetics and Developmental Biology

  • Long Article
  • Published:
Biological Theory Aims and scope Submit manuscript

    We’re sorry, something doesn't seem to be working properly.

    Please try refreshing the page. If that doesn't work, please contact support so we can address the problem.

Abstract

Many of the current comparisons of taxic phylogenetic and biological homology in the context of morphology focus on what are seen as categorical distinctions between the two concepts. The first, it is claimed, identifies historical patterns of conservation and variation relating taxa; the second provides a causal framework for the explanation of this conservation and variation. This leads to the conclusion that the two need not be placed in conflict and are in fact compatible, having non-competing epistemic purposes or mapping the same extensions in the form of monophyletic groupings (see Roth, The biological basis of homology 1–26, 1988; Sluys, J Zool Syst Evol Res 34:145–152, 1996; Abouheif, Trends Ecol Evol 12:405–408, 1997; Brigandt, J Exp Zool 299:9–17, 2003, Biol Philos 22:709–725, 2007; Assis and Brigandt, Evol Biol 36:248–255, 2009). This article argues that moves in this direction miss the essential disagreement between these concepts as they have been developed in the context of the debate concerning the best concept for evolutionary investigation. We should rather see these concepts employing a common fundamental methodological approach to homology, but disagreeing about how to apply the methodology effectively. Both concepts employ class reasoning, which pursues homologies as units of generalization—more precisely, as sources of reliable and relevant group-bound information in the form of shared underlying causes. The dispute can be better understood by two poles that structure such reasoning: the need for a reliable basis for projections about the causal history of shared structures, and the desire to identify homologous characters with more informative and specific causal information relevant to generalizing about evolutionary processes. Judgments in favor of one or the other in turn have affected the scope or extension of these competing homology concepts.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This debate begins with the papers of van Valen (1982) and Patterson (1982) setting forward the different biological and phylogenetics perspectives respectively, and involves developmental biologists and phylogenists such as Roth (1984, 1988, 1991), Wagner (1989a, b, 1994, 1999), Rieppel (1992, 1994), Hall (1994, 2007), Müller (2003), Abouheif (1997), and recently, very provocatively, Cracraft (2005).

  2. West-Eberhard (2003) takes there to be universal agreement on this point. That would be nice if it were true but there are certainly many authors who have questioned the association between similarity and homology, such as Bock (1963), Mayr (1969), or in more modern contexts, Lauder (1994) and Kluge (2003), for different reasons. The taxic homology stream I focus on here, which begins with Patterson (1982) and includes authors such as Rieppel and Kearney (2007) and Franz (2005), argues strongly, citing practice itself against the impracticability of removing similarity assessments from primary homology judgments. There has to be some basis for deciding which structures to relate for testing. On this basis, sameness as criterion for homology, which is often asserted by developmental biologists (see Müller 2003) as principal, seems to mean no more than similarity due to common ancestry, both sharing the implication that there is shared information or similarities underlying the grouping as a result of this ancestry. I do not see any principal need to be critical of the use of “similarity” rather than “sameness” here.

  3. I will make a distinction between transformational and strict transformational here, since the notion is ambiguous in the literature. Transformational is often used to mean that elements of process are used as criteria for homology. It is often applied to biological homology. This does not, however, deny treatment of homologies as classes or kinds, as we shall see. Strict transformational I take to be the position asserting an “individualist” ontology, treating homologies as parts of a whole, which need not share any similarities other than historical relations. It fits a particular phylogenetic approach that is popular in the molecular context but is argued with strongly when it comes to morphology.

  4. This association was made earlier by Peters (1973) and Wiley (1975). Patterson is usually cited, however, as the first to rigorously argue for it. Synapomorphies are traits shared by two or more taxa and their most recent common ancestor. There is no gap in the expression or presence of the trait throughout the clade.

  5. See, for instance, as just a selection of literature on this: Assis and Brigandt 2009; Brigandt 2003, 2007; Müller 2003; Minelli 1996, 1999, 2009; West-Eberhard 2005; Haszprunar 1992; Abouheif 1997; Wagner 1989a, b, 1994, 1999; Sluys 1996; Roth 1988; Rieppel 1992, 1994, 2006; Cracraft 2005; Laubichler 2000; Young 1993; Butler and Saidel 2000; Donoghue 1992; de Pinna 1991; Hall 1994, 1999; Roth 1988, 1994; Janies and DeSalle 1999; Striedter 1998, 1999; Striedter and Northcutt 1991; Wake 1994.

  6. Of course, this is not uncontroversial among phylogenists, some of whom would rather disconnect cladistics from any evolutionary interpretation; but it again reflects the views of those taking part in this debate, who are principally concerned with generating platforms for evolutionary study.

  7. A symplesiomorphy is a trait shared between two or more taxa, but also shared with other taxa that have an earlier last common ancestor with the taxa under consideration. Parallelisms are traits arising independently in different lineages. A recurrent trait is a trait that disappears and reappears sporadically amongst related taxa.

  8. This concept is also applied in Newman and Müller (2010).

  9. As an anonymous reviewer pointed out to me, Arendt and Reznick (2007) do not explicitly discuss monophyletic groups or synapomorphic characters. They work to show that the distinction between convergent and parallel evolution is a false dichotomy, representing rather a continuum. But they do pick out examples of features amongst closely related taxa. Such features ordinarily would be considered the result of homologous developmental or gene pathways (p. 27). There is in fact a steady record of discoveries of homologous features that do not map to shared developmental mechanisms. See de Beer (1971), Wagner and Misof (1993), and West-Eberhard (2003).

References

  • Abouheif E (1997) Developmental genetics and homology: a hierarchical approach. Trends Ecol Evol 12:405–408

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Abouheif E (1999) Establishing homology criteria for regulatory gene networks: prospects and challenges. In: Hall BK (ed) Homology. Novartis Foundation Symposium 222. Wiley, Chichester, pp 207–225

  • Arendt J, Reznick D (2007) Convergence and parallelism reconsidered: what have we learned about the genetics of adaptation? Trends Ecol Evol 23:26–32

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Assis LCS, Brigandt I (2009) Homology: homeostatic property cluster kinds in systematics and evolution. Evol Biol 36:248–255

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bechly G (2005) Glossary of phylogenetic systematics. http://www.bernstein.naturkundemuseum-bw.de/odonata/glossary.htm. Accessed 25 July 2005

  • Bock W (1963) Evolution and phylogeny in morphologically uniform groups. Am Nat 97:265–285

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bolker JA, Raff RA (1996) Developmental genetics and traditional homology. BioEssays 18:489–494

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boyd R (1999) Kinds, complexity and multiple realization. Philos Stud 95:67–98

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brigandt I (2003) Homology in comparative, molecular, and evolutionary developmental biology. J Exp Zool 299:9–17

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brigandt I (2007) Typology now: homology and developmental constraints explain evolvability. Biol Philos 22:709–725

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Butler AB, Saidel WM (2000) Defining sameness: historical, biological, and generative homology. BioEssays 22:846–853

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cartmill M (1994) A critique of homology as a morphological concept. Am J Phys Anthropol 94:115–123

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cracraft J (2005) Phylogeny and evo-devo: characters, homology, and the historical analysis of the evolution of development. Zoology 108:345–356

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Beer G (1971) Homology, an unsolved problem. Oxford University Press, London

    Google Scholar 

  • De Pinna MCC (1991) Concepts and tests of homology in the cladistic paradigm. Cladistics 7:367–394

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Donoghue MJ (1992) Homology. In: Keller EF, Lloyd EA (eds) Keywords in evolutionary biology. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, pp 170–179

    Google Scholar 

  • Farris J (1979) The information content of the phylogenetic system. Syst Biol 28:483–519

    Google Scholar 

  • Fitzhugh K (2006) The “requirement of total evidence” and its role in phylogenetic systematics. Biol Philos 21:309–351

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fitzhugh K (2008) Abductive inference: implications for “Linnean” and “phylogenetic” approaches for representing biological systematization. Evol Biol 35:52–82

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Franz NM (2005) Outline of an explanatory account of cladistic practice. Biol Philos 20:489–515

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goodman N (1983) Fact, fiction and forecast. Harvard University Press, Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths PE (2007) The phenomena of homology. Biol Philos 22:643–658

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hall BK (1994) Introduction. In: Hall BK (ed) Homology. Academic Press, San Diego, pp 2–17

    Google Scholar 

  • Hall BK (1999) Introduction. In: Hall BK (ed) Homology. Novartis Foundation Symposium 222. Wiley, Chichester, pp 1–4

  • Hall BK (2007) Homoplasy and homology: dichotomy or continuum. J Hum Evol 52:473–479

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haszprunar G (1992) The types of homology and their significance for evolutionary biology and phylogenetics. J Evol Biol 5:13–25

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Janies D, DeSalle R (1999) Development, evolution and corroboration. Anat Rec 257:6–14

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kluge A (2003) The repugnant and mature in phylogenetic inference: atemporal similarity and historical identity. Cladistics 19:356–368

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laubichler MD (2000) Homology in development and the development of the homology concept. Am Zool 40:777–788

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lauder GV (1994) Homology, form and function. In: Hall BK (ed) Homology. Academic Press, San Diego, pp 152–197

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayr E (1969) Principles of systematic zoology. McGraw-Hill, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Meyer A (1999) Homology and homoplasy: the retention of genetic programmes. In: Hall BK (ed) Homology. Novartis Foundation Symposium 222. Wiley, Chichester, pp 141–157

  • Mickevich MF (1978) Taxonomic congruence. Syst Zool 27:143–158

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Minelli A (1996) Some thoughts on homology 150 years after Owen’s definition. Mem Soc Ital Sci Nat Mus Civ Stor Nat Milano 27:71–79

    Google Scholar 

  • Minelli A (1999) Comparative issue: homology, homoplasy and evolution in functional adaptation. In: Savazzi E (ed) Functional morphology of the invertebrate skeleton. Wiley, New York, pp 15–24

    Google Scholar 

  • Minelli A (2009) Phylo-evo-devo: combining phylogenetics with evolutionary developmental biology. BMC Biol 7:36–38

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Müller GB (2003) Homology: the evolution of morphological organization. In: Müller GB, Newman SA (eds) Origination of organismal form: beyond the gene in developmental and evolutionary biology. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 51–69

    Google Scholar 

  • Müller GB, Wagner GP (1996) Homology, hox genes, and developmental integration. Am Zool 36:4–13

    Google Scholar 

  • Nelson G (1994) Homology and systematics. In: Hall BK (ed) Homology. Academic Press, San Diego, pp 102–151

  • Nelson G, Platnick N (1981) Systematics and biogeography: cladistics and vicariance. Columbia University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Newman SA, Müller GB (2010) Morphological evolution: epigenetic mechanisms. In: Encyclopedia of the life sciences (ELS), www.els.net. Wiley, Chichester

  • Owen R (1843) Lectures on comparative anatomy and physiology of the invertebrate animals. Royal College of Surgeons. Longman, Brown, Green and Longman, London

  • Patterson C (1982) Morphological characters and homology. In: Joysey KA, Friday AE (eds) Problems of phylogenetic reconstruction. Academic Press, London, pp 21–74

    Google Scholar 

  • Peters DS (1973) Homologie—ein Wort und viele Begriffe. Aufsätze und Reden der Senckenbergischen Naturforschenden Gesellschaft 24:173–175

    Google Scholar 

  • Rieppel O (1992) Homology and logical fallacy. J Evol Biol 5:701–715

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rieppel O (1994) Homology, topology, and typology: the history of modern debates. In: Hall BK (ed) Homology. Academic Press, San Diego, pp 64–101

    Google Scholar 

  • Rieppel O (2006) Modules, kinds, and homology. J Exp Zool 304B:18–27

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rieppel O, Kearney M (2002) Similarity. Biol J Linn Soc 75:59–82

  • Rieppel O, Kearney M (2007) The poverty of taxonomic characters. Biol Philos 22:95–113

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roth LV (1984) On homology. Biol J Linn Soc 22:13–29

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roth LV (1988) The biological basis of homology. In: Humphries CJ (ed) Ontogeny and systematics. Columbia University Press, New York, pp 1–26

    Google Scholar 

  • Roth LV (1991) Homology and hierarchies: problems solved and unresolved. J Evol Biol 4:167–194

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roth LV (1994) Within and between organisms: replicators, lineages, and homologues. In: Hall BK (ed) Homology. Academic Press, San Diego, pp 302–338

    Google Scholar 

  • Sluys R (1996) The notion of homology in current comparative biology. J Zool Syst Evol Res 34:145–152

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spemann H (1915) Zur Geschichte und Kritik des Begriffs der Homologie. In: Chun C, Johanssen W (eds) Allgemeine Biologie. Teubner, Leipzig, pp 63–68

  • Striedter GF (1998) Stepping into the same river twice: homologues as recurring attractors in epigenetic landscapes. Brain Behav Evol 52:218–231

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Striedter GF (1999) Homology in the nervous system: of characters, embryology and levels of analysis. In: Hall BK (ed) Homology. Novartis Foundation Symposium 222. Wiley, Chichester, pp 158–172

  • Striedter GF, Northcutt RG (1991) Biological hierarchies and the concept of homology. Brain Behav Evol 38:177–189

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tautz D (1998) Debatable homologies. Nature 395:17–18

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Valen L (1982) Homology and causes. J Morphol 173:305–312

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wagner GP (1989a) The biological homology concept. Annu Rev Ecol Evol Syst 21:15–69

    Google Scholar 

  • Wagner GP (1989b) The origin of morphological characters and the biological basis of homology. Evolution 43:1157–1171

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wagner GP (1994) Homology and mechanisms of development. In: Hall BK (ed) Homology. Academic Press, San Diego, pp 274–301

    Google Scholar 

  • Wagner GP (1999) A research programme for testing the biological homology concept. In: Hall BK (ed) Homology. Novartis Foundation Symposium 222. Wiley, Chichester, pp 125–140

  • Wagner GP, Misof BY (1993) How can a character be developmentally constrained despite variation in developmental pathways? J Evol Biol 6:449–455

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wake D (1994) Comparative terminology. Science 265:268–269

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • West-Eberhard MJ (2003) Developmental plasticity and evolution. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiley EO (1975) Karl Popper, systematics and classification: a reply to Walter Bock and other evolutionary taxonomists. Syst Zool 24:233–243

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Young B (1993) On the necessity of an archetypal concept in morphology, with special reference to the concepts of “structure” and “homology.” Biol Philos 8:225–248

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

This research was funded with a postdoctoral fellowship at the Konrad Lorenz Institute for Evolution and Cognition Research (Altenberg, Austria).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Miles MacLeod.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

MacLeod, M. How to Compare Homology Concepts: Class Reasoning About Evolution and Morphology in Phylogenetics and Developmental Biology. Biol Theory 6, 141–153 (2011). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13752-012-0020-z

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13752-012-0020-z

Keywords

Navigation