1 Introduction

Some theorists hold that a statue and a piece of clay that coincide throughout their existence are identical, although a statue and a piece of clay that coincide for the first part of their existence, and then diverge (or, more generally, a statue and a piece of clay coincident for only part of their existence) are distinct entities. These ‘contingent identity theorists’ thus hold that permanent coincidence is identity, although temporary coincidence is not identity. (E.g., Gibbard 1975; Lewis 1971, 1986, Ch. 4; Noonan 1991, 1993.)Footnote 1

These theorists find it intolerable to suppose that a statue and a piece of clay could completely coincide throughout their existence, sharing all their matter and microphysical parts, and yet fail to be identical. However, they also hold that it is possible for a numerically distinct statue and piece of clay to coincide merely temporarily. For in the case of merely temporary coincidence, they maintain, the statue and the piece of clay have different properties (for example they exist at different times and places), and hence, by Leibniz’s Law, are numerically distinct.

It seems hard to deny that the persistence conditions for statues are significantly different from the persistence conditions for pieces of clay. For example, it seems that the persistence conditions for statues preclude a statue’s continuing to exist if it is radically reshaped, whereas the persistence conditions for pieces of clay allow a piece of clay to survive such a radical reshaping—indeed require it to survive such a radical reshaping, as long as its matter is retained in one coherent mass. Similarly, it seems that the persistence conditions for statues allow a statue to survive a replacement of its matter that would destroy the piece of clay that constitutes it.

Obviously, the contingent identity theorist is committed to the view that it is possible for a single entity to have the persistence conditions of both a statue and a piece of clay. But what, if anything, is problematic about this supposition? Why shouldn’t a single entity have both the persistence conditions of a statue and those of a piece of clay, even if these persistence conditions are different? For although different, why suppose that they are incompatible?

In this paper, I shall do the following. First, I shall show (Sects. 2 and 3) that if persistence conditions were exhausted by de dicto modal principles, there need be nothing problematic about the view that the persistence conditions for statues and pieces of clay, although different, are compatible. A problem of compatibility arises only if the persistence conditions for statues and pieces of clay are taken to have a de re modal aspect as well as a de dicto modal aspect.

In the remainder of the paper (Sects. 46), I discuss the standard response of the contingent identity theorist to this ‘de re modal challenge’. The standard response is that even if persistence conditions do have a de re aspect as well as a de dicto aspect, the appearance of incompatibility that this creates is, in fact, deceptive.

The contingent identity theorist’s strategy [the ‘Abelardian’ strategy, as I shall call it, following Harold Noonan (1991, 1993)] is controversial. Rather than survey well known objections, however, I shall raise a challenge to the strategy that as far as I know has not been discussed in the literature. My challenge, which I call ‘the vacuous satisfaction argument’, concerns whether the Abelardian strategy does justice to our intuitions that the modal implications of persistence conditions cannot be captured by purely de dicto principles.

2 De dicto persistence conditions

For simplicity, I shall assume, without argument, that both statue and piece of clay are sortal concepts, and moreover that they are substance sortals: sortals that apply to an object throughout its existence if they apply to it at any time in its existence.Footnote 2

Substance sortals are, by definition, what have been called ‘necessarily permanent’ properties (Parsons 2005, p. 9), where a necessarily permanent property is one that obeys the principle (NP):

(NP) Necessarily (for all x, if x is (an) F at any time in its existence, then x is (an) F at all times in its existence).

It is important to note that (NP) is a de dicto principle, not a de re principle. (NP) is silent on the question whether a thing that is (an) F in one possible world is also (an) F in other possible worlds. As a consequence, if something is a necessarily permanent property it does not follow that it is an essential property, in the standard sense according to which an essential property of an object is one that it could not have existed without having, or has in all possible worlds in which it exists. In fact, it is obvious that there are necessarily permanent properties that are not essential properties in this sense, such as the property of being a permanent bachelor (defined as being a male human being who in fact never marries) or the property of originating in New Zealand.Footnote 3

On the assumption that statue is a substance sortal, we have the following de dicto principle (S)(1):

(S)(1) Necessarily (for all x, if x is a statue at any time in its existence, then x is a statue at all times in its existence).

But as well as being necessarily permanent, the sortal statue appears to provide ‘passing away conditions’ and ‘preservation conditions’, represented by de dicto principles such as the following:

(S)(2) Necessarily (for all x, if x is a statue, then, if the matter that constitutes x at t is radically reshaped at t, x then ceases to exist).

(S)(3) Necessarily (for all x, if x is a statue, then, if a small portion of the matter that constitutes x at t is removed and immediately replaced by exactly similar matter, and no other change is made to x, x survives).

Like (S)(1), (S)(2), and (S)(3) are de dicto modal principles. They appear to have, by themselves, no de re modal implications.Footnote 4 If so, they have no implications for the modal properties of things that are statues and pieces of clay. (S)(1), (S)(2), and (S)(3) appear to be silent on the question whether a thing that is a statue in one possible world is a statue in other possible worlds.

Suppose that the persistence conditions of statues and pieces of clay can be represented entirely by de dicto modal principles, such as those above and the following (for pieces of clay):

(P)(1) Necessarily (for all x, if x is a piece of clay at any time in its existence, then x is a piece of clay at all times in its existence).

(P)(2) Necessarily (for all x, if x is a piece of clay, then, if the matter that constitutes x at t is radically reshaped at t but preserved in one coherent mass, x survives).

The persistence conditions for statues and pieces of clay represented by these de dicto principles are evidently different. And they are evidently potentially conflicting. If some entity is subjected to a radical reshaping of its matter in which all the matter is preserved in one coherent mass, then it cannot satisfy all of the de dicto principles (S)(1), (S)(2), (P)(1) and (P)(2).Footnote 5

However—at least if we interpret the conditionals in the de dicto principles as material conditionals—this need represent no difficulty for the contingent identity theory. The theory holds that it is only in a permanent coincidence case that a statue and a piece of clay are identical. And, of course, in any permanent coincidence case, the statue (i.e., the piece of clay, according to the contingent identity theorist) is not subjected to a radical reshaping of its matter. Hence it satisfies, vacuously, the antecedent of the conditional ‘if the matter that constitutes x at t is radically reshaped at t, x then ceases to exist’ in (S)(2), and also the antecedent of the conditional ‘if the matter that constitutes x at t is radically reshaped at t but preserved in one coherent mass, x survives’ in (P)(2). Thus the contingent identity theorist can accept all of the de dicto persistence conditions represented by (S)(1), (S)(2), (P)(1), and (P)(2), while still consistently holding that a single entity can be both a statue and a piece of clay, as long as the conditionals in the de dicto principles are read as material conditionals. In sum: on this reading, the de dicto persistence conditions, although potentially conflicting, are perfectly compatible, and can be satisfied by one and the same entity, just as the contingent identity theory requires.

At this point, it may be suggested that it is inappropriate to interpret the conditionals in the de dicto principles (S)(2) and (P)(2) in this fashion.Footnote 6 Interpreted as non-material conditionals, they may require more, for their truth, than the falsity of their antecedents; if so, the argument for the compatibility of the de dicto persistence conditions for statues and pieces of clay given above is undermined.

While this is true, I propose to leave this possibility aside. The reason is that, if the conditionals in the de dicto principles (S)(2) and (P)(2) are given an interpretation that makes the persistence conditions they imply for statues and pieces of clay genuinely incompatible, as opposed to merely potentially conflicting, I think this can only be because, on this interpretation, the de dicto principles are interpreted as having de re modal implications. Rather than explore the complications this interpretation would involve, I propose, for simplicity, to interpret the de dicto principles, from now on, as involving material conditionals, and hence as having, by themselves, no de re modal implications. This might be called the ‘pure de dicto’ interpretation of principles such as (S)(2) and (P)(2).

3 Beyond the de dicto: persistence conditions and de re modality

The conclusion of the previous section is that, on the assumption that the persistence conditions for statues and pieces of clay are exhausted by de dicto principles with no de re modal implications, there need be no genuine conflict (incompatibility) between the persistence conditions for statues and pieces of clay.

However, most theorists suppose that the persistence conditions for statues and pieces of clay do have an additional de re modal aspect. In particular, many theorists hold that, even in a permanent coincidence case, both of the following de re statements are true:

(1M) The statue could not have been subjected to a radical reshaping of its matter without being destroyed;

(2M) The piece of clay could have been subjected to a radical reshaping of its matter without being destroyed.

(1M) and (2M) are, clearly, de re modal statements. They go beyond the de dicto principles listed above: (1M) goes beyond (S)(2), and (2M) goes beyond (P)(2).Footnote 7 For example, consider the contrast between (1M) and (S)(2). Whereas (S)(2), being a de dicto principle, is silent on the question whether a statue is still a statue in other possible worlds, (1M) appears to imply that it is—that in different possible worlds it is still a statue, and hence is destroyed by radical reshaping in those worlds.Footnote 8

With the addition of these de re statements (if taken to represent implications of the persistence conditions of statues and pieces of clay), there really is, now, a challenge of compatibility that the contingent identity theorist needs to answer. The addition of the ‘de re persistence conditions’ represented by (1M) and (2M) threatens to transform the merely potential conflict of de dicto persistence conditions into an actual conflict of modal properties. For, on the face of it, (1M) and (2M) appear to attribute incompatible modal properties to the statue and the piece of clay, thus entailing that, by Leibniz’s Law, the statue and the piece of clay are not identical, even in a permanent coincidence case.

Nor, it is worth emphasizing, is the problem confined to the claim that there is a change that the statue could not have survived although the piece of clay could, or vice versa. For example, even if we are sceptical about (1M), if we accept an apparently more modest counterfactual claim, such as:

(3M) If the statue had been subjected to a radical reshaping of its matter (including one in which all its matter was preserved in one coherent mass), then it would have been destroyed,

this still appears to lead to a conflict, in combination with (4M):

(4M) If the piece of clay had been subjected to a radical reshaping of its matter in which all its matter was preserved in one coherent mass, then it would have survived.

The counterfactual statements (3M) and (4M), although different from (1M) and (2M), are still de re. And (3M) and (4M) also appear to attribute to the statue and the piece of clay incompatible modal properties: in this case incompatible counterfactual properties (being such that it would not have survived a radical reshaping, and being such that it would have survived a radical reshaping).

4 The contingent identity theory and de re modal statements: the Abelardian strategy

Notoriously, contingent identity theorists respond to this ‘de re challenge’ by adopting the theory that modal predicates are what Noonan (1991, 1993) has called ‘Abelardian’ predicates, where an Abelardian predicate is one that can stand for different properties depending on the subject term to which it is attached. The most familiar version of this strategy is probably the ‘inconstant’ version of counterpart theory advocated by David Lewis in ‘Counterparts of Persons and Their Bodies’ (1971) and subsequently in On the Plurality of Worlds (1986). According to Lewis’s version of the strategy, we may interpret (1M) as:

(1M*) The statue has no statue-counterparts that are subjected to a radical reshaping of their matter without being destroyed,

and interpret (2M) as:

(2M*) The piece of clay has piece-of-clay counterparts that are subjected to a radical reshaping of their matter without being destroyed.

There is no obvious problem about claiming that (1M*) and (2M*) are both true, even if the statue and the piece of clay are identical. If the statue is identical with the piece of clay, then it has both statue-counterparts (i.e., counterparts under the statue counterpart relation) and piece-of-clay counterparts (counterparts under the piece-of-clay counterpart relation). But (according to the Abelardian theory) it is the statue-counterparts that are invoked by referring to it as ‘the statue’, whereas it is the piece-of-clay counterparts that are invoked by referring to it as ‘the piece of clay’.Footnote 9

Evidently, if this Abelardian strategy is successful, the contingent identity theorist can agree that the persistence conditions associated with being a statue and being a piece of clay are not exhausted by de dicto principles, but also have de re implications, and also that their de re implications include the truth of such pairs of de re statements as (1M) and (2M), and (3M) and (4M). For if the strategy is successful, the contingent identity theorist can nevertheless maintain that, in spite of the apparent modal difference represented by these de re modal statements, there is no genuine difference in modal properties between the statue and the piece of clay in the permanent coincidence case.

5 Does the Abelardian theorist do justice to the de re significance of persistence conditions?

The Abelardian strategy has come under attack on semantic grounds, from Kit Fine (2003). In this paper, however, I shall pursue a different line of argument. This is to question whether this strategy really does justice to our intuition that, for example, the statue could not, while the piece of clay could, have survived a radical reshaping.

5.1 The explanation argument

One argument for the conclusion that the Abelardian strategy does not do justice to this intuition appeals to the following considerations.Footnote 10 I shall call this ‘the explanation argument’. Can the Abelardian theorist give an adequate explanation of why, in a temporary coincidence case in which a statue is subjected to a radical reshaping in which all its matter is preserved in one coherent mass, the statue does not survive, whereas the piece of clay with which it has so far coincided throughout its existence does survive? Doesn’t the explanation of why the statue and the piece of clay ‘go their separate ways’ in the temporary coincidence case require a genuine difference in their modal properties, and not merely an apparent difference? And if so, does this not undermine the claim that the apparent difference in the modal properties of the statue and the piece of clay in the permanent coincidence case is merely apparent?

In spite of its superficial plausibility, though, this ‘explanation argument’ against the Abelardian strategy (and the contingent identity theory) is, I think, unsuccessful, for reasons given by Harold Noonan (2013).Footnote 11 Consider a statue, Statue, and a piece of clay, Piece, which coincide from the very beginning of their existence until a later time at which their matter is radically reshaped but remains in one coherent mass. The de dicto principles (S)(2) and (P)(2), together with (S)(1) and (P)(1), entail that, when the radical reshaping occurs, Statue goes out of existence, whereas Piece survives. The proponent of the explanation argument claims that this entailment is insufficient to explain the phenomena, and that a satisfactory explanation must appeal to a difference in the modal properties of Statue and Piece in the temporary coincidence case. In response, Noonan argues (to my mind convincingly) that this explanatory demand depends on the illegitimate assumption that the explananda in question—for example, that Statue goes out of existence when it is radically reshaped—require a causal explanation. Of course, a causal explanation is required for why the matter of Statue is radically reshaped. But in connection with the further question: ‘why did the radical reshaping of the matter of Statue put an end to Statue’s existence?’, the demand for a causal explanation is misguided. No causal explanation of the fact that the radical reshaping means the demise of Statue is either required or even appropriate. An entirely satisfactory explanation of why the radical reshaping of Statue’s matter, when it occurs, puts an end to Statue’s existence, is provided by the fact that Statue is a statue, together with the de dicto principles (S)(1) and (S)(2).Footnote 12

There is, however, a different argument for the conclusion that the Abelardian theory does not do justice to the de re aspect of the persistence conditions relevant to the items in a permanent coincidence case, an argument that has not, as far as I am aware, been discussed in the literature. To this argument I now turn.

5.2 Vacuous satisfaction and the inadequacy of de dicto principles

The argument—which, for reasons I hope will become apparent, I shall call ‘the vacuous satisfaction argument’—is an argument for the conclusion that the Abelardian strategy defeats the purpose of introducing de re conditions into the persistence conditions for statues and pieces of clay.

The vacuous satisfaction argument begins by noting that, as we have seen, it is crucial to the defence of the contingent identity theory that there is nothing in the de dicto persistence conditions of statues and pieces of clay that rules out their being possessed by one and the same entity. Suppose, though, that it were to turn out (as I shall suggest it does) that the reason why we think there is a de re aspect to persistence conditions, in addition to the de dicto aspect, is precisely that we think the de dicto principles alone make it too easy for something to be both a statue and a piece of clay. If that were the reason for insisting on further de re principles, the Abelardian strategy would obviously be undermined.

To see this, consider some uncontroversial cases where it is clear that the modal implications of a concept cannot be captured by de dicto principles alone, and where part of the reason for this is appears to be that the relevant de dicto principles can be, in a sense, vacuously satisfied. For example, consider the properties of bravery and cowardice. And consider the following de dicto modal principles that might be taken to represent some of their modal implications—principles analogous (in certain respects) to the de dicto modal principles that apply to statues and pieces of clay:

(B) Necessarily (for all [persons] x, x is brave only if, if x is confronted with danger, x stands firm).

(C) Necessarily (for all [persons] x, x is a coward only if, if x is confronted with danger, x runs away).

The description of the behaviour associated with bravery and cowardice given in the principles (B) and (C) is, of course, absurdly simplistic, and hence open to obvious counterexamples. But even if this were not so, the (de dicto) principles (B) and (C) would still fail to do justice to the modal difference between bravery and cowardice, for a quite different reason. The reason is that there is nothing in the necessary conditions for bravery and cowardice specified in these principles (standing firm if confronted with danger, and running away if confronted with danger) to prevent a single person from satisfying both of them trivially (or vacuously).Footnote 13 All it takes is that the person be fortunate enough to avoid being confronted with a situation of danger. And this fails to capture the overwhelmingly plausible intuition that if a person S is brave, then even if S is never confronted with danger, it is true that if he had been, he would have behaved in certain ways—for example that he would have stood firm, rather than running away. But to say that a brave person S would have done such a thing is to make de re modal claim (more specifically, a de re counterfactual claim) about S. Similarly, we have an overwhelmingly plausible intuition that the claim that someone is a coward has certain de re counterfactual implications: for example, that the person would have run away if confronted with danger.Footnote 14

But—and here is the crucial point—suppose that the reason why we think such additional de re conditions are needed in order to capture the modal difference between bravery and cowardice is that it is ‘too easy’ for someone to satisfy the de dicto conditions (B) and (C) for being both brave and a coward, by doing so ‘vacuously’. If so, it would defeat the purpose of insisting on these additional de re conditions if they were to be reconstrued, in Abelardian fashion, in such a way as to make it equally easy for someone to satisfy the de re conditions too. For example, if to say:

(CM) Wimpy William would have run away if he had been confronted with danger,

and

(BM) Brave Bill would have stood firm if he had been confronted with danger

is just to say something about what Wimpy William’s cowardly counterparts do, and about what Brave Bill’s brave counterparts do, then the combination of (CM) and (BM) does not rule out—any more than does the combination of (B) and (C)—the possibility that Wimpy William and Brave Bill are the same person, a person who is both brave and cowardly.

The same structure is evident when we consider other dispositions, such as solubility. Intuitively, the modal conditions necessary for being (water-) soluble and for being (water-) insoluble are not exhausted by the merely de dicto principles:

(WS) Necessarily (for all x)(x is (water-) soluble only if, if x is put in water, x dissolves).

(WI) Necessarily (for all x)(x is (water-) insoluble only if, if x is put in water, x does not dissolve).

Why so? This is because, even if we ignore other potential inadequacies in these principles,Footnote 15 it is obviously possible for something to satisfy, trivially and vacuously, both the necessary condition for being soluble and the necessary condition for being insoluble represented by the de dicto principles (WS) and (WI). All it takes is for the thing never to be put in water. Yet clearly we think that part of what is involved, modally, in being soluble is that if something is soluble, then even if it never is put in water, if it had been, it would have dissolved. And this, of course, is a de re claim. Similarly, we think that part of what is involved, modally, in being insoluble is that if something is insoluble, then even if it never is put in water, if it had been, it would not have dissolved—again, a de re claim.Footnote 16 Once again, though, the Abelardian strategy, if applied here, would undermine the prospect of treating these de re conditions as representing a modal difference between solubility and insolubility that the de dicto principles fail to capture. For, example, if such de re conditions are interpreted in terms of an Abelardian counterpart theory, and the same entity can have both soluble and insoluble counterparts, which are invoked by referring to it in different ways, then it might be the case that for some entity x, and some description ‘D’, of x, the de re counterfactual statement: ‘If D had been put in water, it would have dissolved’ is true, while for some other description, ‘D*’, of the very same entity x, the de re counterfactual statement ‘If D* had been put in water, it would not have dissolved’ is also true.

To sum up: I have suggested that there are cases of certain properties (in my examples, certain dispositional properties), where all of the following are true:

  1. (1)

    Purely de dicto modal principles are insufficient to do justice to the modal implications of these properties.

  2. (2)

    This is because the conditions involved in the relevant de dicto modal principles can be, in a sense, vacuously satisfied.

  3. (3)

    An appeal to certain de re modal statements captures the modal implications that the de dicto principles fail to capture in these ‘vacuous satisfaction’ cases.

    But, crucially,

  4. (4)

    The truth of (3) requires that the relevant de re modal statements are construed as involving the non-Abelardian predication of modal properties (in particular, certain counterfactual properties).

But what bearing does this have on the application of the contingent identity theorist’s Abelardian strategy to the case of the permanently coincident statue and piece of clay? As I indicated at the beginning of this section, the relevance is this. It is, I suggest, very plausible to suppose that the reason why we think that the persistence conditions for statues and pieces of clay must involve a de re aspect—why we must ‘go beyond the de dicto’ in order to do justice to their persistence conditions—is precisely that it is ‘too easy’ for something to satisfy merely de dicto persistence conditions such as those discussed in Sect. 2 above. It is too easy, for example, to satisfy both (S)(2) (a condition for being a statue) and (P)(2) (a condition for being a piece of clay), by doing so ‘vacuously’. But if this is correct, the Abelardian strategy for the interpretation of de re modal predicates, applied to this case, is in conflict with the very motivation for insisting that an account of the persistence conditions of statues and pieces of clay in terms of de dicto principles alone is inadequate, and that it needs supplementation with de re principles. I call this argument against the Abelardian contingent identity theorist ‘the vacuous satisfaction argument’.Footnote 17

Before proceeding, I need to counter an objection.Footnote 18 The reader might wonder whether there is a significant difference between the vacuous satisfaction argument, which I endorse, and the ‘explanation argument’ mentioned in Sect. 5.1 above, which I claim to reject. My response is that there is a significant difference between the arguments, one which allows me consistently to accept the first and reject the second. The explanation argument rests on the assumption that a genuine difference in modal properties is required to explain why, in a temporary coincidence case, a statue fails to survive a change that the piece of clay that coincides with it for the first part of its existence does not. This is the assumption criticized by Noonan. By contrast, my vacuous satisfaction argument does not require the attribution of this explanatory role to the genuine difference in modal properties in temporary coincidence cases. Instead, what drives my vacuous satisfaction argument is the thesis that, even if we restrict our attention solely to permanent coincidence cases, a genuine difference in modal properties is required to match our intuitions.

This response to the objection would, of course, be inadequate if it were the case that the intuitions lying behind both arguments are essentially the same. However, I maintain that this is not so. Consider the intuition that my vacuous satisfaction argument appeals to. This ‘too easy’ intuition is that there is a modal difference that prevents a statue from being identical with a piece of clay that purely de dicto principles cannot capture, because it is consistent with the joint satisfaction of the de dicto principles for being a statue and being a piece of clay. The mere fact that a statue and piece of clay would have behaved differently in certain circumstances is enough to ensure that they are not identical, even if those circumstances never arise.

It is true that, if we do think that there is such a de re modal difference between statues and pieces of clay—a genuine difference in their modal properties—we might be tempted to give this de re modal difference a further explanatory role. If my counter to the explanation argument is correct, that would be a mistake. But this further step is not mandatory. Hence my vacuous satisfaction argument represents a way of isolating an intuition that there is a genuine difference in modal properties between statues and pieces of clay that is independent of any explanatory role that might be attributed to this difference. (For my response to the charge that, thus construed, my vacuous satisfaction argument begs the question against the contingent identity theorist, see the next section.)

6 Conclusion

If successful, my ‘vacuous satisfaction argument’ shows that there is an important respect in which the Abelardian contingent identity theory fails to do justice to our de re modal intuitions: namely, that the theory’s treatment of de re modality is at odds with the very intuitions that lead us to think that a purely de dicto theory of the persistence conditions associated with sortal concepts is inadequate. My vacuous satisfaction argument does, however, require, for its defence, a defence of my claim that the justification for thinking that the modal implications of the persistence conditions for statues and pieces of clay are not exhausted by de dicto principles (such as those discussed in Sect. 2 above) depends on the fact that those de dicto principles can be jointly satisfied by being vacuously satisfied. Although I think this claim is plausible, it requires more defence than I can provide here. I do, however, want to end by proposing a challenge to the Abelardian contingent identity theorist who would deny this claim. This challenge is important, inter alia, in attempting to rebut the charge that my vacuous satisfaction argument simply begs the question against the contingent identity theorist.

The Abelardian contingent identity theorist accepts that, in order to do justice to the persistence conditions for statues and pieces of clay, we must accept that these persistence conditions do have de re implications [such as (1M) and (2M), and (3M) and (4M) (Sect. 3 above)] that go beyond the purely de dicto (although of course they argue that these further de re implications can be reconciled with the contingent identity theory). But—and here is the challenge—what good reason does the Abelardian contingent identity theorist have for agreeing that the persistence conditions for statues and pieces of clay have such additional de re implications at all? Why not suppose, instead, that the persistence conditions for statues and pieces of clay are exhausted by purely de dicto persistence conditions, and that no further de re element is involved?

Reflecting on the legacy of Quine’s scepticism about de re modality, John Divers has pressed, on behalf of the Quinean (or other) de re modal sceptic, the question what the point of de re modality is, and ‘why we should struggle to accommodate de re modalizing in our total theory’ (2007, p. 57). The attempt at the accommodation of the de re that is most prominent in Divers’s paper is, however, that of David Lewis, with its employment of an ‘inconstant’ (and Abelardian) version of counterpart theory. The discussion in my paper suggests that, at least with regard to modal questions concerning persistence, the Lewisian may be particularly ill-placed to answer Divers’s challenge. If my vacuous satisfaction argument concerning the rationale for the introduction of a de re element to the persistence conditions for things such as statues and pieces of clay is correct, the Lewisian accommodation may be achieved only at the cost of sacrificing what rationale there is for regarding purely de dicto persistence conditions as inadequate.

When confronted with the contingent identity theorists’ Abelardian attempt to accommodate the apparent de re implications of sortal concepts, I think many people’s initial reaction is to suspect that the contingent identity theorist has merely paid lip-service to the phenomena, without doing justice to the intuitions that lie behind them: in effect, that an Abelardian account of de re modality does not take de re modality seriously. If I am right, then this suspicion, at least in the case of the apparent de re modal consequences of sortal concepts and their persistence conditions, is justified.