Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-dnltx Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-23T13:18:10.855Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Definition and Reduction

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  14 March 2022

Edward H. Madden*
Affiliation:
San Jose State College

Abstract

While I do not accept any current analysis of theoretical terms I also reject certain criticisms of them. Specifically, I reject the criticism that the paradoxes of material implication and the counterfactual problem eliminate the explicit definition view; and I also reject the criticism that explicitly defined theoretical terms do not refer to anything which “really exists” or do not have “excess meaning.” I do argue, however, that the explicit definition view confuses and conflates the concepts of criterion and meaning analysis. I also defend reduction sentences against the counterfactual difficulty, but show, too, how this view is already logically committed to the network or postulational view of meaning. Finally, I show how the concept of reduction sentences confuses in several ways the concepts of criterion and meaning analysis—although not in quite the same way as explicit definitions do.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Philosophy of Science Association 1961

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

[1] Barker, S. F., Induction and Hypothesis (Ithaca, New York: Cornell University Press, 1957).Google Scholar
[2] Bergmann, Gustav, “The Logic of Psychological Concepts,” Philosophy of Science, 18 (1951), 93110.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[3] Bergmann, Gustav, The Metaphysics of Logical Positivism (New York: Longmans, Green and Co., 1954).Google Scholar
[4] Bergmann, Gustav, Philosophy of Science (Madison, Wisconsin: University of Wisconsin Press, 1957).Google Scholar
[5] Bergmann, Gustav, “Theoretical Psychology,” Annual Review of Psychology, 4 (1953), 435458.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
[6] Braithwaite, R. B., Scientific Explanation (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1953).Google Scholar
[7] Carnap, Rudolf, “The Methodological Character of Theoretical Concepts” in Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Vol. I. (Minneapolis, Minnesota: University of Minnesota Press, 1956).Google Scholar
[8] Carnap, Rudolf, “Testability and Meaning,” Philosophy of Science, 3 (1936), 420-68; 4 (1937), 140.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[9] Chisholm, Roderick M., “Law Statements and Counterfactual Inference,” Analysis 15 (1955), 97-105. Reprinted in Madden, Edward H., The Structure of Scientific Thought (Boston: Houghton Mifflin Co., 1960), pp. 229235.Google Scholar
[10] Feigl, Herbert, “Existential Hypotheses,” Philosophy of Science, 17 (1950), 3562.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[11] Hempel, Carl G., Fundamentals of Concept Formation in the Empirical Sciences (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1952).Google Scholar
[12] Hempel, Carl G., “The Theoretician's Dilemma” in Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Vol. II, (Minneapolis, Minnesota: University of Minnesota Press, 1958).Google Scholar
[13] Hempel, Carl G., and Oppenheim, Paul, “Studies in the Logic of Explanation,” Philosophy of Science, 15 (1948), 135175.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[14] Jack, Henry, “Reply to Barker's Criticism of Formalism,” Philosophy of Science, 26 (1959), 355361.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[15] Koehler, Wolfgang, Dynamics in Psychology (New York: Liveright Publishing Co., 1940).Google Scholar
[16] MacCorquodale, K., and Meehl, P. E., “On a Distinction between Hypothetical Constructs and Intervening Variables,” Psychological Review, 55 (1948), 95107.10.1037/h0056029CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
[17] Madden, Edward H., “The Enthymeme: Crossroads of Logic, Rhetoric, and Metaphysics,” Philosophical Review, LXI (1952), 368376.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[18] Madden, Edward H., “A Logical Analysis of ‘Psychological Isomorphism’,” The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 8 (1957), 177191.10.1093/bjps/VIII.31.177CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[19] Madden, Edward H., “The Nature of Psychological Explanation,” Methodos, 9 (1957), 111.Google Scholar
[20] Madden, Edward H., “Philosophy of Science in Gestalt Theory,” Philosophy of Science, 19 (1952), 228-38. Reprinted in Feigl, H. and Brodbeck, M., Readings in the Philosophy of Science (New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts, 1953), 559570.Google Scholar
[21] Mandler, George and Kessen, William, The Language of Psychology (New York: John Wiley and Sons, 1959).Google Scholar
[22] Marx, M. H., “Intervening Variable or Hypothetical Construct?,” Psychological Review, 58 (1951), 235247.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
[23] Pap, Arthur, “Disposition Concepts and Extensional Logic” in Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Vol. II, (Minneapolis, Minnesota: University of Minnesota Press, 1958).Google Scholar
[24] Putnam, Hilary, “Review of Gustav Bergmann's Philosophy of Science,” Philosophical Review, LXIX (1960), 276–77.Google Scholar
[25] Salmon, Wesley, and Nakhnikian, George, “‘Exists’ as a predicate,” Philosophical Review, LXVI (1957), 535541.Google Scholar
[26] Scriven, Michael, “Definitions, Explanations, and Theories” in Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Vol. II, (Minneapolis, Minnesota: University of Minnesota Press, 1958).Google Scholar
[27] Spence, Kenneth W., “The Differential Response in Animals to Stimuli Varying within a Single Dimension,” Psychological Review, 44 (1937), 430444.CrossRefGoogle Scholar