Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-75dct Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-20T11:30:03.167Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Place of The Self in Contemporary Metaphysics1

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  07 July 2015

Rory Madden*
Affiliation:
University College London

Abstract

I explain why the compositionalist conception of ordinary objects prevalent in contemporary metaphysics places the manifest image of the human self in a precarious position: the two theoretically simplest views of the existence of composites each jeopardize some central element of the manifest image. I present an alternative, nomological conception of ordinary objects, which secures the manifest image of the human self without the arbitrariness that afflicts compositionalist attempts to do the same. I close by sketching the consequences of the recommended position for the traditional personal identity debate about the nature and persistence of human selves.

Type
Papers
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy and the contributors 2015 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

1

Thanks to the audience at the Royal Institute of Philosophy for their comments and questions, and to Nicholas K. Jones for discussion.

References

2 Parfit, Derek, ‘We Are Not Human Beings’, Philosophy 87 (2012), 528 CrossRefGoogle Scholar. Olson, Eric, ‘Parfit on Human Beings’, in Mind, Self and Person edited by O'Hear, Anthony (Cambridge University Press, forthcoming)Google Scholar

3 Representatives of this tradition include many of the biggest names in contemporary metaphysics: Lewis, David, The Plurality of Worlds (Blackwell, 1986)Google Scholar, van Inwagen, Peter, Material Beings (Cornell University Press, 1990)Google Scholar, Fine, Kit, ‘Things and Their Parts’, Midwest Studies in Philosophy XXIII (1999)Google Scholar, Sider, Ted, Four-Dimensionalism (Oxford University Press, 2001)CrossRefGoogle Scholar, Koslicki, Kathrin, The Structure of Objects (Oxford University Press, 2008).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

4 The terminology ‘arranged K-wise’ is van Inwagen's (Material Beings, 109), picking out a potentially complex relational condition distinctive of the parts of Ks, a condition which may be met by pluralities of different cardinalities (as pluralities of different cardinalities may each be arranged in a circle). But it should be noted that compositionalism is not as such committed to the position that the nature of an ordinary thing is fundamentally to be explained in terms of a relation among parts. An alternative is to think of an ordinary thing as generated by a certain function or operation upon given things, in the way one could think of a set as generated by the application of the operation of ‘set-building’ to some given elements. There need be no metaphysically illuminating relation among the elements of a set so generated (see Fine, Kit, ‘Towards a Theory of Part’, Journal of Philosophy 107 (2010), 559589 CrossRefGoogle Scholar). In what follows ‘things arranged K-wise’ will be used loosely, to cover both things being related in a certain way distinctive of the parts of Ks, and things being input to a generative operation in a way distinctive of Ks.

5 Sellars, Wilfrid, ‘Philosophy and the Scientific Image of Man’, in Sellars, Wilfrid, Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul Ltd, 1963), 140 Google Scholar

6 Sellars, ‘Philosophy and the Scientific Image of Man’, 20

7 Ibid., 6

8 Sellars, ‘Philosophy and the Scientific Image of Man’, 19

9 See Fine, ‘Things and Their Parts’, for the view that ordinary material things are ‘rigid embodiments’ or ‘variable embodiments’, composites in some respects more set-like in their character than classical mereological sums.

10 For expressions of the view that it would be arbitrary to deny that ordinary objects form a vanishingly small subset of a massively plenitudinous class, see Yablo, Stephen, ‘Identity, Essence and Indiscernibility’, Journal of Philosophy 84 (1987), 293314 CrossRefGoogle Scholar, Fine, ‘Things and Their Parts’, Hawthorne, John, Metaphysical Essays (Oxford University Press, 2006)CrossRefGoogle Scholar

11 For examples of restrictive theories of composition see Van Inwagen, Material Beings, and Hoffman, Gary and Rosenkrantz, Joshua, Substance: its Nature and Existence (Routledge, 1996)CrossRefGoogle Scholar

12 This is an instance of the so-called Problem of the Many. See Unger, PeterThe Problem of the Many’, Midwest Studies in Philosophy V (1980), 411467 CrossRefGoogle Scholar

13 For this eliminativist view see Dorr, Cian and Rosen, Gideon, ‘Composition as Fiction’, in The Blackwell Guide to Metaphysics edited by Gale, Richard (Blackwell, 2002)Google Scholar, and Sider, TedAgainst Parthood’ in Oxford Studies in Metaphysics Volume 8, edited by Bennett, Karen and Zimmerman, Dean (Oxford University Press, 2013), 237–93Google Scholar

14 Zimmerman and Unger have each in effect suggest that immaterialism is required in order to save the manifest image of the human self from the overpopulation worries that beset materialist views. See Zimmerman, Dean, ‘Material People’, in The Oxford Handbook of Metaphysics, edited by Loux, Michael and Zimmerman, Dean (Oxford University Press, 2003)Google Scholar, and Unger, Peter, ‘The Mental Problem of the Many’, in Oxford Studies in Metaphysics volume 1, edited by Zimmerman, Dean (Oxford University Press, 2004), 195222 Google Scholar

15 Sider, ‘Against Parthood’, mounts a tenacious defence of the position that the ideological economy of eliminativism about composites defeats ordinary appearances to the contrary.

16 See Fine, KitEssence and Modality’, Philosophical Perspectives 8 (1994), 116 Google Scholar

17 See Bennett, Karen, ‘Spatio-Temporal Coincidence and The Grounding Problem’, Philosophical Studies 118 (2004), 339371 CrossRefGoogle Scholar

18 On multiple realizability and the autonomy of the special sciences see Fodor, Jerry, ‘Special Sciences (Or: The Disunity of Science as a Working Hypothesis)’, Synthese 28 (1974), 97115 CrossRefGoogle Scholar

19 I do not mean to suggest that there are no broadly compositionalist approaches to the grounding problem on the market. On the ‘four-dimensionalist’ view that ordinary objects have temporal parts as well as spatial parts, a difference in parts can be found between (temporarily) coinciding objects (See Lewis, The Plurality of Worlds, and Sider, Four-Dimensionalism). The ‘hylomorphic’ view that ordinary objects have formal parts as well as material parts also permits a difference in parts between coinciding objects (See Koslicki, The Structure of Objects, and Fine, Kit, ‘Coincidence and Form’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume LXXXII (2008), 101118 CrossRefGoogle Scholar). But I believe that in the light of the availability of a non-compositionalist picture of ordinary objects, the appeal to differences in (intuitively unfamiliar) parts starts to look like a theory-driven, Procrustean attempt to force the facts into a compositionalist mould.

20 Dennett, Daniel, ‘Real Patterns’, Journal of Philosophy 88 (1991), 2751 CrossRefGoogle Scholar

21 See Jones, Nicholas K., ‘Multiple Constitution’, Oxford Studies in Metaphysics volume 9, edited by Bennett, Karen and Zimmerman, Dean (Oxford University Press, forthcoming)Google Scholar for a detailed presentation of an ‘Aristotelian’ solution to the Problem Of The Many in roughly this spirit. The view that ordinary objects are individuated by nomological activity along a spatio-temporal path is developed extensively in Wiggins, David, Sameness and Substance Renewed (Cambridge University Press, 2001)CrossRefGoogle Scholar

22 Fodor, Jerry, ‘Special Sciences: Still Autonomous After All These Years’, Philosophical Perspectives 11 (1997), 149163 Google Scholar

23 Van Inwagen, Material Beings, Snowdon, Paul, ‘Persons, Animals, and Ourselves’ in The Person and the Human Mind (Clarendon, 1990)Google Scholar, Olson, Eric, The Human Animal (Oxford University Press, 1997)Google Scholar

24 For a classic statement of a neo-Lockean view, see Shoemaker, Sydney, ‘Personal Identity: A Materialist's Account’, in Shoemaker, Sydney and Swinburne, Richard, Personal Identity (Blackwell, 1984)Google Scholar

25 It is an interesting question, to be left for another occasion, what the naturalist should say about a ‘fission’-type case, in which a human is not whittled down to a cerebrum but is instead divided into cerebrum and otherwise intact cerebrum-complement.