Skip to main content
Log in

What Not to Make of Recalcitrant Emotions

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Erkenntnis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Recalcitrant emotions are emotions that conflict with your evaluative judgements, e.g. fearing flying despite judging it to be safe. Drawing on the work of Greenspan (Emotions and Reasons, Routledge, London, 1988) and Helm (Emotional Reason, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2001), Brady (Philos Stud 145:413–430, 2009) argues these emotions raise a challenge for a theory of emotion: for any such theory to be adequate, it must be capable of explaining the sense in which subjects that have them are being irrational. This paper aims to raise scepticism with this endeavour of using the irrationality shrouding recalcitrant episodes to inform a theory of emotion. I explain (1) how ‘recalcitrant emotions’ pick out at least two phenomena, which come apart, and (2) that there are different epistemic norms relevant to assessing whether, and if so how, subjects undergoing recalcitrant bouts are being irrational. I argue these factors result in differing accounts of the precise way these emotions make their bearers irrational, which in turn frustrates present efforts to adjudicate whether a given theory of emotion successfully meets this challenge. I end by briefly exploring two possible ways a philosophy of emotion might proceed in the face of such scepticism.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Proponents of the view include Solomon (1980) and Nussbaum (2001).

  2. Also see Deonna and Teroni (2012: Sect. 5) and Benbaji (2013).

  3. A judgementalist might be able to explain emotional recalcitrance without positing contradicting judgements, e.g. a subject judges that flying is safe but still feels fear because what he actually fears is not flying itself, but the prospect of flying. This point due to Solomon, is mentioned, though not examined, by D’Arms and Jacobson (pg. 129, fn.6). Also see Grzankowski (2016), who explains how judgementalists can deny attributions of radical irrationality by claiming that subjects endorse conflicting contents under different concepts or different modes of presentation.

  4. E.g. D’Arms and Jacobson describe it as a “familiar psychological phenomenon” (2003: 129).

  5. There are other exceptions, e.g. Rorty (1978) provides in-depth examples when discussing emotional akrasia, and Dillon (1997) does likewise in her analysis of self-respect. These examples also run-together groundless emotions with emotions that involve conflict.

  6. This model of emotion generation should give judgementalists cause for concern, but they could respond that emotional responses generated via circuit (i) won’t legitimately count as emotions because they lack the relevant evaluative judgements which help individuate them from similar responses.

  7. I am grateful to an anonymous referee for this suggestion.

  8. See Weiskrantz (1986) for an overview.

  9. This provides a causal explanation of the conflict, but it doesn't resolve one of the key controversies shrouding emotional recalcitrance, viz. the precise nature of this conflict.

  10. Neo-judgementalists include de Sousa (1987), Helm (2001) and Roberts (2003), whereas Jamesians include James (1890/1950), Lang (1922) and Prinz (2004).

  11. See Tappolet (Tappolet 2012: Sect. 1.5) for a response. Brady (2013: 112) also offers a different, sparser, explanation of the irrationality: recalcitrant bouts are irrational because nothing about the object or event constitutes adequate reason for the emotion. As I read Brady, this is supposed to augment his earlier account. Very roughly, recalcitrant episodes are irrational because they involve searching for “reasons that bear on the accuracy of our emotional construals, despite the fact that we have endorsed the opposing evaluative view in judging as we do” (2013: 177).

  12. Döring also mentions and rejects two further principles, one she ascribes to Tappolet (pg. 393) and the other to Helm (pg. 396).

  13. This account of emotions involving justificatory reasons is discussed in more detail in Brady (2007).

  14. Damasio’s (1994) Somatic-Marker Hypothesis proposes a similar thesis. Very roughly, somatic states, i.e. feelings about the body that are associated with past experiences, assist deliberation by highlighting some options as either favourable or unfavourable.

  15. Another form of strategic irrationality is due to Döring, who explains the intuition that recalcitrant emotions make us irrational on grounds that they interfere with “the reasoned pursuit of our goals” (2014: 128).

  16. I am grateful to an anonymous referee for this suggestion.

  17. Also see Faucher and Tappolet (2007, 2008), and Majeed (2019).

References

  • Benbaji, H. (2013). How is recalcitrant emotion possible? Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 91, 1–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brady, M. S. (2007). Recalcitrant emotions and visual illusions. American Philosophical Quarterly, 44(3), 273–284.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brady, M. S. (2009). The irrationality of recalcitrant emotions. Philosophical Studies, 145, 413–430.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brady, M. S. (2013). Emotional insight: The epistemic role of emotional experience. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Broome, J. (2013). Rationality through reasoning. Malden, MA: Blackwell.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • D’Arms, J., & Jacobson, D. (2003). The significance of recalcitrant emotion. In A. Hatzimoysis (Ed.), Philosophy and the emotions (pp. 127–145). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Damasio, A. R. (1994). Descartes’ error: Emotion, rationality and the human brain. New York: Putnam.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Sousa, R. B. (1987). The rationality of emotion. Cambridge and London: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Deonna, J. A., & Teroni, F. (2012). The emotions: A philosophical introduction. London and New York: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dillon, R. S. (1997). Self-respect: Moral, emotional, political. Ethics, 107(2), 226–249.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Döring, S. A. (2014). Why recalcitrant emotions are not irrational. In R. Roeser & C. Todd (Eds.), Emotion and value (pp. 124–136). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Döring, S. A. (2015). What’s wrong with recalcitrant emotions? Dialectica, 69(3), 381–402.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Faucher, L. and Tappolet, C. (2007). Facts and values in emotional plasticity. In L. Charland & P. Zachar (Eds.), Fact and value in emotion; consciousness and emotion book series (pp. 101–137). Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Faucher, L. and Tappolet, C. (2008). The modularity of emotions. Alberta: University of Calgary Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greenspan, P. S. (1981). Emotions as evaluations. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 62, 158–169.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greenspan, P. S. (1988). Emotions and reasons. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, P. E. (1997). What emotions really are. Chicago and London: Chicago University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Grzankowski, A. (2016). The real trouble with recalcitrant emotions. Erkenntnis, 82(3), 641–651.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Helm, B. (2001). Emotional reason. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • James, W. (1890/1950). The principles of psychology. New York: Dover.

  • Lang, C. G. (1922). The emotions. Translated by I. A. Haupt. Baltimore, MD: Williams and Wilkins.

  • LeDoux, J. E. (1996). The emotional brain: The mysterious underpinnings of emotional life. New York: Simon & Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

  • Majeed, R (2019). Does modularity undermine the pro-emotion consensus? Mind and Language.

  • McDowell, J. (2009). Wittgensteinian “quietism”. Common Knowledge, 15(3), 365–372.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M. (2001). Upheavals of thought: The intelligence of emotions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Prinz, J. J. (2004). Gut reactions: A perceptual theory of the emotions. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roberts, R. (2003). Emotions: An essay in aid of moral psychology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, A. O. (1978). Explaining emotions. Journal of Philosophy, 75, 139–161.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Solomon, R. (1980). Emotions and choice. In A. Rorty (Ed.), Explaining emotions (pp. 251–281). Los Angeles: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tappolet, C. (2012). Emotions, perceptions, and emotional illusions. In C. Clotilde (Ed.), Perceptual illusions. Philosophical and psychological essays (pp. 207–224). Palgrave-Macmillan: Basingstoke and New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tappolet, C. (2017). Emotions, values, and agency. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weiskrantz, L. (1986). Blindsight: A case study and implications. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Raamy Majeed.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Majeed, R. What Not to Make of Recalcitrant Emotions. Erkenn 87, 747–765 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-019-00216-0

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-019-00216-0

Navigation