A philosophical view on concepts in psychiatry

https://doi.org/10.1016/j.ijlp.2009.12.006Get rights and content

Abstract

This essay first outlines a philosophical theory of concepts and then applies it to two areas of relevance to psychiatrists, especially forensic psychiatrists. In the philosophical theory, the respective roles of verbal and non-verbal definitions are illuminated, and the importance of the phenomenon of division of semantic labour is stressed. It is pointed out that vagueness and ambiguity of a term often result when the term is used for several practical purposes at the same time. Such multi-purpose uses of terms may explain both the current problems associated with the Swedish forensic–psychiatric concept of a severe mental disorder and some of the shortcomings of DSM-IV.

Introduction

What could, and should, philosophy do for psychiatry? A not uncommon answer to this question is that philosophers should scrutinize and analyze central psychiatric concepts, criticize these concepts if they do not fulfil their tasks in communication, and then if possible suggest improvements of them. We agree that these are proper aims for the philosophy of psychiatry. However, the tasks of conceptual scrutiny, analysis, criticism and reform – let us use the term “conceptual investigations” as a general term – can each be carried out in several different ways. This is partly due to the fact that what you take a conceptual investigation to be depends on what you think a concept is and how you think a concept works. Therefore, we have decided to allocate a fair space in the beginning of this paper to a discussion about concepts and to state our own view of what a concept and a conceptual investigation is. After that we will give two examples from psychiatry where conceptual investigations by philosophers might be of value. The first of these concerns the concept of severe mental disorder,1 which plays a central role in Swedish forensic psychiatry and has been subject to ongoing critical discussions for years. The second example concerns the nature of the DSM-IV categories.

Section snippets

What is a concept?

Although it is a basic function of language to convey information about states of affairs that hold in the real world, and although an important function of words is to refer to real objects, the functions of language can to a remarkable degree be uncoupled from these states of affairs and objects. In short, there are false statements and descriptions of non-existing objects. The sentence “It's raining here and now”, uttered in plain sunshine does not refer to any fact, but still we clearly

Ostensive definitions

How are terms given their meaning? Definitions, in the sense of statements expressing necessary and sufficient conditions for the application of a term, undoubtedly play an important role in fixing the meaning of terms where this is needed.3

What is a concept?

The authors of this essay support a so-called realistic standpoint concerning scientific categories and dimensions. This entails that the conceptual scheme can and should mirror the real world. Depression or anxiety (to use two psychiatric examples) are hence not regarded as social or theoretical constructs but as real entities (maybe of the continuous kind) existing in the world outside theories and concepts. Our concepts are formed while we are interacting with these natural phenomena.

When are concepts different?

Laymen and experts, as well as experts from different fields, differ widely in how much they know, what they know, and what theories they have about the phenomena which their concepts apply to. This does not necessarily hinder them from communicating important facts among themselves about these phenomena. E.g., in order to prevent a suicide the psychoanalyst can warn the biological psychiatrist that her patient has a deep depression. This can work (i.e., proper decisions can be taken) even if

The division of semantic labour

To demand that members of linguistic communities always have exactly the same understanding of the words they use when exchanging information would be too much. Experts and laymen would never be able to successfully communicate if that were to be the case. This is where different depths of understanding come into play.

In linguistic communities that are not too homogeneous, the depth of understanding of common terms often varies widely, with the experts in the field usually having clear and

Meaning, knowledge and goals

Until now, we have mainly spoken of cases in which conceptual differences, if there are such, do not lead to any disagreement in practice. Of course, there are also conceptual differences that do lead to disagreement over actual classifications. We will now describe an important source of such differences and disagreement.

The basic function of linguistic tools to enhance decisions implies that our concepts – what our words mean – are often determined by our goals, what we strive to achieve.

“Severe mental disorder”

According to the current Swedish system concerning treatment of mentally disturbed criminal offenders, which has been in use since 1965, criminal offenders may be sentenced to involuntary psychiatric care as an alternative to prison. Which of these two options is chosen depends on whether the act is judged to have occurred under the influence of a severe mental disorder (SMD for short). If the answer is positive, there is a prison prohibition. However, this need not entail psychiatric care. If

The multiple roles of DSM-III/IV

The diagnostic labels in DSM-III (APA, 1980) and DSM-IV (APA, 1994) are excellent examples of terms serving several different practical functions at the same time. Our main agenda here is not primarily to point out the conceptual problems with the DSM,17 but rather to give a suggestive explanation to why the diagnostic system does not work

Concluding remarks

Conceptual analysis is much more than contemplating on one's own intuitions about the meaning of the terms in question. This is because concepts are not to be found “in the head”. Instead the conceptual analyst must study how a given term is used by people in concrete communication. Such a study should focus on two aspects. First, the analyst must look for the practical functions, the different roles the term plays in actual communication. Second, she must get acquainted with the phenomena that

References (17)

  • American Psychiatric Association

    Diagnostic and statistical manual of mental disorders

    (1980)
  • American Psychiatric Association

    Diagnostic and statistical manual of mental disorders

    (1994)
  • American Psychiatric Association

    Diagnostic and statistical manual of mental disorders

    (2000)
  • F. Belfrage

    Brottsligheten, psykiatrin och samhället

    (1995)
  • G. Csibra et al.

    Natural pedagogy

    Trends in Cognitive Sciences

    (2009)
  • M. First

    Experience with the Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders and preparations for the future

  • A. Horwitz et al.

    The loss of sadness: How psychiatry transformed normal sorrow into depressive disorder

    (2007)
  • H. Malmgren

    Psychiatric classification: The status of so-called “diagnostic criteria”

There are more references available in the full text version of this article.

Cited by (7)

  • Introducing a standard of legal insanity: The case of Sweden compared to The Netherlands

    2015, International Journal of Law and Psychiatry
    Citation Excerpt :

    One important aspect of the Wittgensteinian view is that conceptual ambiguity may be the result of conflicts about the communicative goals of a certain discussion. In this specific context the goals and practices of psychiatrists and lawyers respectively may be diverging; for instance, as Malmgren, Radovic, Thorén, and Haglund (2010) argue, the psychiatrists could be partly concerned about the outcome of the verdict in terms of psychiatric treatment, while the question of legal responsibility is the judges' focus (this depends on the jurisdiction, and, more precisely, on the specific tasks of both the psychiatrist and the judge in a criminal case). In fact, to reach a decision about a defendant's sanity a translation has to take place from the psychiatric findings (medical domain) to the notion of insanity (legal domain).

  • Mentally disordered criminal offenders in the Swedish criminal system

    2010, International Journal of Law and Psychiatry
    Citation Excerpt :

    Schizophrenia, for instance, is always severe with regard to kind but need not be severe with regard to degree, whereas depression is not severe with regard to kind but may be severe with regard to degree. It has been suggested that the lack of a clear definition of the concept of a severe mental disorder has made it possible to interpret it as a mental disorder causing inaccountability (Malmgren, Radovic, Thorén, & Haglund, 2010). The new legislation was also ambiguous (not to say contradictory) regarding severe personality disorders.

  • Focus on psychosis

    2015, Dialogues in Clinical Neuroscience
View all citing articles on Scopus
View full text