Skip to main content
Log in

Superexplanations for counterfactual knowledge

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

I discuss several problems for Williamson’s counterfactual-theory of modal knowledge and argue that they have a common source, in that the theory neglects to elucidate the proper constraints on modal reasoning. Williamson puts forward an empirical hypothesis that rests on the role of counterfactual reasoning for modal knowledge. But he overlooks central questions of normative modal epistemology. In order for counterfactual reasoning to yield correct beliefs about modality, it needs to be suitably constrained. I argue that what is needed is, specifically, information concerning the nature or essence of things. By integrating this information, essentialist deduction arguably provides a better account of our knowledge of modality. Furthermore, I argue that essences have distinctive causal and explanatory powers—indeed, essences are superexplanatory for how things are. Compared to Williamson’s counterfactual-theory, superexplanatory essentialism clarifies what the proper constraints on modal reasoning are, and why they have such a special status.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. I will mostly speak of knowledge of modality. However, what I say should be applicable to more modest epistemological targets, such as justified belief or understanding of modality, and to be neutral enough to accommodate internalist as well as externalist broader epistemological perspectives.

  2. Note that the criteria for what counts as a correct supposition or scenario may thus vary depending on whether we are considering practical everyday possibility, or rather metaphysical possibility, as the relevant constraints may vary (more below). Talk of “correctness” here refers to modal truth broadly understood.

  3. In quantified contexts, the following two equivalences also hold:

    (N)q

    □A ≡ ∀p (p □→ A)

    i.e., something is necessary IFF whatever were the case, it would still be the case,

    and

    (P)q

    ◊A ≡ ∃p ¬ (p □→ ¬A)

    i.e., something is possible IFF it is not such that it would fail in every eventuality (159).

  4. Similarly, Jenkins (2008) has argued that, even granted that the logical equivalences hold, it does not follow that we know metaphysical modality through the same cognitive processes by which we know counterfactuals.

  5. Along analogous lines, Ichikawa (2016) points out that Williamson's equivalences could be used to define any type of modality.

  6. Thanks to an anonymous referee for pressing this objection.

  7. Thanks to David Papineau for helpful discussion of this point.

  8. Thanks to an anonymous referee for pushing me on this.

  9. I take principle (E) to be a priori like Kripke (1980) originally suggested. For further discussion: Jago (2018); Mallozzi (2018a); and Vaidya and Wallner (2018).

  10. Of course this does not imply that the many superficial features and behaviors that are caused by the essence are also necessary. Those could easily vary due to environmental conditions (in fact even at the actual world, in exceptional cases, they do), or by assuming that certain laws might have been different.

  11. The ideas in this section are further developed in unpublished work with Marion Godman and David Papineau.

  12. Papineau (2013) makes a similar point. Interestingly, though, he concedes that intuitions of possibility are in general philosophically important not as a source of evidence for or against our theories, but rather as a means to clarify our thinking.

  13. Thanks to an anonymous referee for pointing this out.

References

  • Berto, F., Ripley, D., Priest, G., & French, R. (2017). Williamson on counterpossibles. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 89, 1–21.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boghossian, P. (2011). Williamson on the a priori and the analytic. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 82, 488–497.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boghossian, P., & Peacocke, C. (2000). New essays on the a priori. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boghossian, P., & Williamson, T. (2020). Debating the a priori. Oxford University Press: Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • BonJour, L. (1998). In defense of pure reason. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brogaard, B., & Salerno, J. (2013). Remarks on counterpossibles. Synthese, 190, 639–660.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bueno, O., & Shalkowski, S. (2015). Modalism and theoretical virtues: Toward an epistemology of modality. Philosophical Studies, 172, 671–689.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. (2002). Does Conceivability Entail Possibility? In T. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Conceivability and possibility (pp. 145–201). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deng, D. M. (2016). On the alleged knowledge of metaphysical modality. Philosophia, 44, 479–495.

    Google Scholar 

  • Devitt, M. (2005). There is No A Priori. In E. Sosa & M. Steup (Eds.), Contemporary debates in epistemology (pp. 105–115). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Devitt, M. (2010). Putting metaphysics first. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine, K. (1994). Essence and modality. Philosophical Perspectives, 8, 1–16.

    Google Scholar 

  • Godman, M., & Papineau, D. (2020). Species have historical not intrinsic essences. In A. Bianchi (Ed.), Language and reality from a naturalistic perspective: Themes from Michael Devitt. Springer: Berlin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Godman, M., Mallozzi, A., & Papineau, D. (2020). Essential properties are super-explanatory. Taming metaphysical modality. The Journal of the. American Philosophical Association. https://doi.org/10.1017/apa.2019.48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gregory, D. (2017). Counterfactual reasoning and knowledge of possibilities. Philosophical Studies, 174, 821–835.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hale, B. (2013). Necessary beings. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hale, B. (2018). Essence and definition by abstraction. Synthese. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-1726-7.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hill, C. (2006). Modality, modal epistemology, and the metaphysics of consciousness. In S. Nichols (Ed.), The architecture of imagination: New essays on pretense, possibility and fiction (pp. 205–236). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ichikawa, J. (2016). Modals and modal epistemology. In A. Kind & P. Kung (Eds.), Knowledge through imagination (pp. 124–144). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ichikawa, J., & Jarvis, B. (2012). Rational imagination and modal knowledge. Noûs, 46, 127–158.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jago, M. (2013). Impossible worlds. Noûs, 47, 713–728.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jago, M. (2018). Knowing how things might have been. Synthese. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-1869-6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jenkins, C. (2008). Modal knowledge, counterfactual knowledge and the role of experience. The Philosophical Quarterly, 58, 693–701.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kind, A., & Kung, P. (Eds.). (2016). Knowledge through imagination. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kment, B. (2014). Modality and explanatory reasoning. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kment, B. (2018). Essence and modal knowledge. Synthese. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-01903-1.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. (1971). Identity and necessity. In M. K. Munitz (Ed.), Identity and individuation (pp. 135–164). New York: New York University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. (1980). Naming and necessity. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kroedel, T. (2012). Counterfactuals and the epistemology of modality. Philosophers Imprint, 12(12), 1–14.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kung, P. (2010). Imagining as a guide to possibility. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 81, 620–663.

    Google Scholar 

  • Langland-Hassan, P. (2016). On choosing what to imagine. In A. Kind & P. Kung (Eds.), Knowledge through imagination (pp. 61–84). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leon, F. (2017). From modal skepticism to modal empiricism. In B. Fischer & F. Leon (Eds.), Modal epistemology after rationalism (pp. 247–262). Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lowe, E. J. (2008). Two notions of being: entity and essence. Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement, 62, 23–48.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lowe, E. J. (2012). What is the source of our knowledge of modal truths? Mind, 121, 919–950.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mallozzi, A. (2018a). Putting modal metaphysics first. Synthese. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-1828-2.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mallozzi, A. (2018b). Two notions of metaphysical modality. Synthese. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-1702-2.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mallozzi, A. (2019). Introduction, in new directions in the epistemology of modality. Special Issue of Synthese. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02358-8.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mallozzi, A. (forthcoming). Imagination, apriority, and modal knowledge. In A. Kind & C. Badura (Eds.), The epistemic uses of imagination. Routledge.

  • Malmgren, A. S. (2011). Rationalism and the content of intuitive judgment. Mind, 120, 263–327.

    Google Scholar 

  • Menzies, P. (1998). Possibility and conceivability: A response-dependent account of their connections. In R. Casati (Ed.), European review of philosophy (Vol. 3, pp. 255–277). New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morato, V. (2017). Conceivability, counterfactual thinking and philosophical exceptionality of modal knowledge. Topoi, 56, 1–13.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nolan, D. (1997). Impossible worlds: A modest approach. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 38, 535–572.

    Google Scholar 

  • Papineau, D. (2013). The poverty of conceptual analysis. In M. C. Haug (Ed.), Philosophical methodology: The armchair or the laboratory? (pp. 166–194). Abingdon and New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peacocke, C. (2011). Understanding, modality, logical operators. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 82, 472–480.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peacocke, C. (2019). The primacy of metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Priest, G. (2016). Thinking the impossible. Philosophical Studies, 173, 2649–2662.

    Google Scholar 

  • Restall, G. (1997). Ways things can’t be. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 38, 583–596.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roca-Royes, S. (2011a). Conceivability and de re modal knowledge. Noûs, 45, 22–49.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roca-Royes, S. (2011b). Modal knowledge and counterfactual knowledge. Logique et Analyse, 54, 537–552.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roca-Royes, S. (2017). Similarity and possibility: An epistemology of de re possibility for concrete entities. In B. Fischer & F. Leon (Eds.), Modal epistemology after rationalism (pp. 221–246). Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spaulding, S. (2016). Imagination through knowledge. In A. Kind & P. Kung (Eds.), Knowledge through imagination (pp. 207–226). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strohminger, M. (2015). Perceptual knowledge of nonactual possibilities. Philosophical Perspectives, 29, 363–375.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tahko, T. E. (2012). Counterfactuals and modal epistemology. Grazer Philosophische Studien, 86, 93–115.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tahko, T. E. (2017). The epistemology of essence. In A. Carruth, S. C. Gibb, & J. Heil (Eds.), Ontology, modality, mind themes from the metaphysics of E. J. Lowe. Oxfod: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomasson, A. (2018). How can we come to know metaphysical modal truths? Synthesehttps://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-1841-5.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vaidya, A. (2017). The epistemology of modality. In Zalta E. (Ed.) The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2017/entries/modality-epistemology/.

  • Vaidya, A., & Wallner, M. (2018). The epistemology of modality and the problem of modal epistemic friction. Synthese. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-1860-2.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Inwagen, P. (1998). Modal epistemology. Philosophical Studies, 92, 67–84.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vetter, B. (2015). Potentiality: From dispositions to modality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vetter, B. (2016). Williamsonian modal epistemology, possibility-based. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 46, 766–795.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2007). The philosophy of philosophy. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2013). How deep is the distinction between a priori and a posteriori knowledge? In A. Casullo & J. Thurow (Eds.), The a priori in philosophy (pp. 291–313). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2016). Knowing by imagining. In A. Kind & P. Kung (Eds.), Knowledge through imagination (pp. 112–123). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Worley, S. (2003). Conceivability, possibility and physicalism. Analysis, 63, 15–23.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yablo, S. (1993). Is conceivability a guide to possibility? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 53, 1–42.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yli-Vakkuri, J. (2013). Modal skepticism and counterfactual knowledge. Philosophical Studies, 162, 605–623.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I am grateful to David Papineau and one anonymous referee at Philosophical Studies for helpful comments on a previous draft of this paper. Thanks also to Michael Devitt, Sonia Roca-Royes, Jonathan Schaffer, Anand Vaidya, and Michael Wallner for helpful conversation.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Antonella Mallozzi.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Mallozzi, A. Superexplanations for counterfactual knowledge. Philos Stud 178, 1315–1337 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-020-01477-0

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-020-01477-0

Keywords

Navigation