Skip to main content
Log in

Assimilation and control: belief at the lowest levels

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The core of Zimmerman’s picture posits an inverse correlation between an action’s automaticity and belief’s role in the action’s execution. This proposal faces serious problems. First, high-attention, high-control actions don’t seem to heighten awareness of one’s beliefs. Second, low-attention, low-control actions are caused by the same states at play when executing high-attention, high-control actions, in which case there is no ontological difference in the states involved in these behaviors. Third, on Zimmerman’s view it is unclear what it is for a state to be involved in behaviors at all, as the basic realist response—that beliefs cause behavior—is unavailable to a Zimmerman-style pragmatist. Lastly, if Zimmerman's view were right and low-level behaviors weren't caused by beliefs, then we should turn our attention to those states instead, as most of our behavior isn’t executed under conditions of high control and attention.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. He seems to scoff at mental representations general, which is of a piece of his general aversion to psychological reality (“an animal’s psychology is its neurology”) (2018, 65).

  2. This situation has nothing to do with nicotine per se—one can find the same effects for alcohol, cocaine, and opioids; see Porot and Mandelbaum (forthcoming).

  3. Zimmerman does not like talk of belief storage (“the belief box”), and he offers up some old canards against it [i.e., there is no neural evidence for localized beliefs, (Zimmerman 72; cf. Quilty-Dunn and Mandelbaum 2018a)]. This makes one wonder if he’d apply the same arguments to semantic memories, thereby showing their putative non-existence. It would be just as sensible for him to do so, for what are semantic memories if not beliefs?

  4. Note that the CRT isn’t in itself interesting. The same morals—and generally the same rates—hold if instead one focuses on syllogistic reasoning or base rate cases (Bago and De Neys 2017).

  5. The book fails to engage with many core questions, such as belief’s functional role (e.g., how beliefs are acquired, changed, stored, and used in inference) and its metaphysics (e.g., whether beliefs are relations to mental representations, where their opacity comes from). When these topics do arise the treatment generally lasts a sentence. For instance, Zimmerman rejects propositional attitude talk entirely, by writing, “Of course, humans use sentences to attribute beliefs to themselves and other animals. But there is no further sense in which belief is itself a ‘propositional attitude’” (p 20). That is the whole argument. For other senses in which belief may be deemed a propositional attitude see Richard (1983), Dretske (1988), Crimmins (1992), Spohn (2012), Gluer and Wikforss (2013), Leitgeb (2017) and Friedman (2019).

References

  • Bago, B., & De Neys, W. (2017). Fast logic?: Examining the time course assumption of dual process theory. Cognition,158, 90–109.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bago, B., & De Neys, W. (2019). The smart system 1: Evidence for the intuitive nature of correct responding on the bat-and-ball problem. Thinking & Reasoning,25(3), 257–299.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bendaña, J., & Mandelbaum, E. (forthcoming). The fragmentation of belief. In C. Borgoni, D. Kinderman, A. Onofri (Eds.) The fragmented mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Braddon-Mitchell, D., & Jackson, F. (1996/2007). Philosophy of mind and cognition. Malden: Blackwell Publishing.

  • Crimmins, M. (1992). Talk about beliefs. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1988). Explaining behavior. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1987). Psychosemantics. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, J. (2019). Inquiry and belief. Noûs,53(2), 296–315.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gluer, K., & Wikforss, A. (2013). Against belief normativity. In T. Chan (Ed.), The aim of belief (pp. 121–146). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gu, X., Terry, L., Salas, R., Baldwin, P., Soltani, A., Kirk, U., et al. (2015). Belief about nicotine selectively modulates value and reward prediction error signals in smokers. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences,112(8), 2539–2544.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leitgeb, H. (2017). The stability of belief. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1972). Psychophysical and theoretical identifications. Australasian Journal of Philosophy,50, 249–258.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mandelbaum, E. (2010). The architecture of belief: An essay on the unbearable automaticity of believing. Doctoral Dissertation, University of North Carolina, Chapel Hill.

  • Mandelbaum, E. (2013). Against alief. Philosophical Studies,165(1), 197–211.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mandelbaum, E. (2014). Thinking is believing. Inquiry,57(1), 55–96.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mandelbaum, E. (2015). Associationist theories of thought. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (summer 2017 edition). Retrived October 1, 2019 from https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2017/entries/associationist-thought/.

  • Mandelbaum, E. (2016). Attitude, inference, association: On the propositional structure of implicit bias. Noûs,50(3), 629–658.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mandelbaum, E. (2019). Troubles with Bayesianism: An introduction to the psychological immune system. Mind and Language,34(2), 141–157.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mandelbaum, E., & Quilty-Dunn, J. (2015). Believing without reason, or: Why liberals shouldn’t watch Fox News. The Harvard Review of Philosophy,22, 42–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Porot, N., & Mandelbaum, E. (forthcoming). Empirical models of belief: A progress report. Wires Cognitive Science.

  • Quilty-Dunn, J. (2017). The syntax and semantics of perceptual representations. Doctoral Dissertation, City University of New York.

  • Quilty-Dunn, J., & Mandelbaum, E. (2018a). Against dispositionalism: Belief in cognitive science. Philosophical Studies,175(9), 2353–2372.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quilty-Dunn, J., & Mandelbaum, E. (2018b). Inferential transitions. Australasian Journal of Philosophy,96(3), 532–547.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Richard, M. (1983). Direct reference and ascriptions of belief. Journal of Philosophical Logic,12, 425–447.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spohn, W. (2012). The laws of belief: Ranking theory and its philosophical applications. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Zimmerman, A. (2018). Belief: A pragmatic picture. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Funding received during the execution of this paper came from the National Endowment of the Humanities fellowship (FEL- 257901-18). The NEH is hereby thanked for their largesse. Special thanks to Susanna Siegel, Kate Ritchie, and Jake Quilty-Dunn for helpful suggestions on this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Eric Mandelbaum.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Mandelbaum, E. Assimilation and control: belief at the lowest levels. Philos Stud 177, 441–447 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-019-01401-1

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-019-01401-1

Keywords

Navigation