Skip to main content
Log in

Expressing and Describing Experiences. A Case of Showing Versus Saying

  • Published:
Acta Analytica Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Experiences are interpreted as conscious mental occurrences that are of phenomenal character. There is already a kind of (weak) intentionality involved with this phenomenal interpretation. A stricter conception of experiences distinguishes between purely phenomenal experiences and intentional experiences in a narrow sense. Wittgenstein’s account of psychological (experiential) verbs is taken over: Usually, expressing mental states verbally is not describing them. According to this, “I believe” can be seen as an expression of one’s own belief, but not as an expression of a belief about one’s belief. Hence, the utterance “I believe it is raining” shows that I believe that it is raining, although it is not said by these words that I believe that it is raining. Thinking thoughts such as “I believe it is raining, but it is not raining” (a variant of Moore’s paradox) is an absurdity between what is already said by silently uttering “It is not raining” and what is shown by silently uttering “I believe it is raining.” The paper agrees with a main result of Wittgenstein’s considerations of Moore’s paradox, namely the view that logical structure, deducibility, and consistency cannot be reduced solely to propositions—besides a logic of propositions, there is, for example, a logic of assertions and of imperatives, respectively.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. In his paper on Russell Moore (1944, 204) characterizes “implying” again: “That we imply it means only, I think, something which results from the fact that people, in general, do not make a positive assertion, unless they do not believe that the opposite is true: people, in general, would not assert positively ‘he has not gone out,’ if they believed that he had gone out. And it results from this general truth, that a hearer who hears me say ‘he has not gone out,’ will, in general, assume that I don’t believe that he has gone out, although I have neither asserted that I don’t, nor does it follow, from what I have asserted, that I don’t. Since people will, in general, assume this, I may be said to imply it by saying ‘he has not gone out,’ since the effect of my saying so will, in general, be to make people believe it, and since I know quite well that my saying it will have this effect.”

  2. In this interpretation the following principle is presupposed:

    Asserting (p and q) entails asserting (p) and asserting (q).

    This does not hold for connections like disjunction and subjunction:

    Asserting (p or q) and asserting (if p then q), respectively, does not entail either asserting (p) or asserting (q).

  3. It is worth noticing that in certain circumstances for a conscious person the failing of a certain mental state is itself a mental state; at least it looks as immediate as the positive case: Usually I do not need inferences from other beliefs and from observation of my own words and behavior in order to express my failing to believe that it is raining.

  4. Williams refers to the following original examples from Moore:

    Type A: “I went to the pictures last Tuesday, but I don’t believe that I did” (Moore 1942, 543)

    and

    Type B: “I believe he has gone out, but he has not” (Moore 1944, 204).

  5. Having called propositions of the form <p & I do not believe that p> Moorean propositions, and assertions of Moorean propositions Moorean assertions, and believings of Moorean propositions Moorean beliefs, Uriah Kriegel (2004, 100) states: “Moore’s paradox, as originally discussed by Moore and Wittgenstein, concerned Moorean assertions exclusively. More recently, philosophers have taken interest in the paradoxical nature of Moorean beliefs as well.” As Wittgenstein’s solution is also applicable to the soliloquy case, I think, Wittgenstein’s investigations of Moore’s paradox concern not only Kriegel’s Moorean assertions but also his so-called Moorean beliefs.

References

  • Chisholm, R. (1989). On metaphysics. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chisholm, R. (1996). A realistic theory of categories: An essay on ontology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kriegel, U. (2004). Moore’s paradox and the structure of conscious belief. Erkenntnis, 61(1), 99–121.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moore, G. E. (1942). A reply to my critics. In P. A. Schilpp (Ed.), The philosophy of G. E. Moore (pp. 533–677). Evanston and Chicago: Northwestern University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, G. E. (1944). Russell’s theory of descriptions. In P. A. Schilpp (Ed.), The Philosophy of Bertrand Russell, Vol. I (pp. 175–225). New York, Evanston, London: Harper and Row, 31963.

  • Rosenthal, D. M. (1995). Self-knowledge and Moore's paradox. Philosophical Studies, 77(2–3), 195–209.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schroeder, S. (2006). Moore’s paradox and first-person authority. In M. Kober (Ed.), Deepening our understanding of Wittgenstein (pp. 161–174). Amsterdam – New York: Rodopi (= Grazer Philosophische Studien, 71).

  • Shoemaker, S. (1995). Moore’s paradox and self-knowledge. Philosophical Studies, 77(2–3), 211–228.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, J. N. (2006). Moore’s paradoxes and conscious belief. Philosophical Studies, 127, 383–414.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, J. N. (1998). Wittgensteinian accounts of Moorean absurdity. Philosophical Studies, 92, 283–306.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1958). Philosophical investigations (2nd ed.). Oxford: Blackwell. (First published 1953.) [= PI I and PI II, respectively].

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1980a). Remarks on the philosophy of psychology (Vol. I). Oxford: Blackwell [= RPP I].

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1980b). Remarks on the philosophy of psychology (Vol. II). Oxford: Blackwell [= RPP II].

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1946). Typed from manuscript Catalogue No. 132. (9. 9. 1946–22. 10. 1946). [= MS 132]

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1949). “MS 169” (around 1949). In L. Wittgenstein, Last Writings on the Philosophy of Psychology, Vol. II, The Inner and the Outer, 1949–1951. 1–49. [= MS 169]

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Johann C. Marek.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Marek, J.C. Expressing and Describing Experiences. A Case of Showing Versus Saying. Acta Anal 26, 53–61 (2011). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-010-0119-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-010-0119-4

Keywords

Navigation