Skip to main content
Log in

Classical Logic is not Uniquely Characterizable

  • Published:
Journal of Philosophical Logic Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

I show that it is not possible to uniquely characterize classical logic when working within classical set theory. By building on recent work by Eduardo Barrio, Federico Pailos, and Damian Szmuc, I show that for every inferential level (finite and transfinite), either classical logic is not unique at that level or there exist intuitively valid inferences of that level that are not definable in modern classical set theory. The classical logician is thereby faced with a three-horned dilemma: Give up uniqueness but preserve characterizability, give up characterizability and preserve uniqueness, or (potentially) preserve both but give up modern classical set theory. After proving the main result, I briefly explore this third option by developing an account of classical logic within a paraconsistent set theory. This account of classical logic ensures unique characterizability in some sense, but the non-classical set theory also produces highly non-classical meta-results about classical logic.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This result is not explicitly stated in [19] or [20], but can be straightforwardly proven from the definition of a function using the “law of ordered pairs” , stated as proposition 5.10 in [19].

References

  1. Barrio, E., Pailos, F., & Szmuc, D. (2019). (Meta)Inferential Levels of Entailment beyond the Tarskian Paradigm. Synthese https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02411-6.

  2. Cook, R. (2007). Embracing revenge: on the indefinite extensibility of language. In J.C. Beall (Ed.) Revenge of the Liar: New Essays on the Paradox.

  3. Barrio, E., & Pailos, F. (2020). A Hierarchy of Classical and Paraconsistent Logics. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 49(1), 93–120.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  4. Brady, R., & Routley, R (1989). The Non-Triviality of Extensional Dialectical Set Theory. In G. Priest, R. Routley, & J. Norman (Eds.) Paraconsistent Logic: Essays on the Inconsistent (pp. 415–436). Munich: Philosophia Verlag.

  5. Brady, R. (2006). Universal Logic. Stanford: California: CSLI.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Carnielli, W., & Coniglio, M.E. (2016). Paraconsistent set theory by predicating on consistency. Journal of Logic Computation, 26, 97–116.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  7. Cobreros, P., La Rosa, E., & Tranchini, L. (2020). (I Can’t Get No) Antisatisfaction. Synthese. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-020-02570-x.

  8. Dicher, B., & Paoli, F. (2019). ST, LP, and Tolerant Metainferences. In C. Başkent T. Ferguson (Eds.) Graham Priest on Dialetheism and Paraconistency. Switzerland: Springer.

  9. Mendelson, E. (2001). Introduction to Mathematical Logic. London: Chapman & Hall/CRC.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Priest, G. (1995). Beyond the Limits of Thought. Cambridge: Cambridge Unviersity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Priest, G. (2006). In contradiction: a study of the transconsistent Expanded ed. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  12. Priest, G. (2013). Indefinite Extensibility—Dialetheic Style. Studia Logica., 101, 1263–1275.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  13. Routley, R. (1977). Ultralogic as Universal. Relevance Logic Newsletter, 2, 50–90 and 138-175. Reprinted in Routley, R. and Weber, Z. (2019) Ultralogic as Universal. Springer, 1–121.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Russell, B. (1905). On some difficulties in the theory of transfinite numbers and order types. Proceedings of the London Mathematical Society, 4, 29–53.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Scambler, C. (2020). Classical Logic and the Strict Tolerant Hierarchy. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 49, 351–370.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  16. Scambler, C. (2020). Transfinite Meta-inferences. Journal of Philosophical Logic. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-020-09548-7.

  17. Absolute Generality.

  18. Tourville, N., & Cook, R.T. (2016). Embracing the technicalities: expressive completeness and revenge. The Review of Symbolic Logic, 9(2), 325–58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  19. Weber, Z. (2010). Transfinite numbers in paraconsistent set theory. The Review of Symbolic Logic, 3(1), 71–92.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  20. Weber, Z. (2012). Transfinite cardinals in paraconsistent set theory. The Review of Symbolic Logic, 5, 269–293.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  21. Weber, Z., Badia, G., & Girard, P. (2016). What Is an Inconsistent Truth Table?. Australasian journal of Philosophy, 94, 533–548.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Isabella McAllister.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Appendix: The Logic and Set Theory of Section 4

Appendix: The Logic and Set Theory of Section 4

The following are logical and set-theoretic axioms, rules, and definitions from [20] (with the addition of an induction axiom) that constitute the background set theory in Section 4 above. I also list the various key facts that are used in proofs of results in Section 4.

Two technical comments about this set theory are in order. First, the logic from [20] differs slightly from that of [19]. In [19], what I list as R3 and R4 below are presented in axiom form, which means that the logic of [20] is slightly weaker. The benefit of choosing the weaker logic is that it is covered by Brady’s non-triviality proof from [4]. However, as Weber points out in a footnote on [20, p. 271], everything from [19] can still be obtained with this weaker logic. Second, I add to the logic of [20] an induction axiom, stating that induction holds of any recursively defined set. While weak forms of transfinite recursion and induction are provable in [19, p. 88], they are just that: weak. To ensure that the recursive definitions of Section 4 are adequately strong, I follow the precedent of Brady [5, ch. 9] and Weber et al. [21] by simply adding an induction axiom to the theory.

  • Logical axioms:

    $$ \begin{array}{@{}rcl@{}} \begin{array}{llll} \mathrm{A}1 & \quad \phi \to \phi \\ \mathrm{A}2 & \quad (\phi \wedge \psi) \to \phi \\ \mathrm{A}3 & \quad (\phi \wedge \psi) \to \psi \\ \mathrm{A}4 & \quad (\phi \wedge (\psi \vee \gamma)) \to ((\phi \wedge \psi) \vee (\phi \vee \gamma)) & \text{(distribution)} \\ \mathrm{A}5 & \quad ((\phi \to \psi) \wedge (\psi \to \gamma)) \to (\phi \to \gamma) & \text{(conjunctive syllogism)}\\ \mathrm{A}6 & \quad ((\phi \to \psi) \wedge (\phi \to \gamma)) \to (\phi \to (\psi \wedge \gamma))\\ \mathrm{A}7 & \quad (\phi \to \neg \psi) \to (\psi \to \neg \phi) & \text{(contraposition)}\\ \mathrm{A}8 & \quad \neg \neg \phi \to \phi & \text{(double negation elimination)}\\ \mathrm{A}9 & \quad \phi \vee \neg \phi & \text{(excluded middle)} \\ \mathrm{A}10 & \quad \forall x \phi \to \phi(y/x) & \text{where } y \text{ is free for } x \text{ in } \phi\\ \mathrm{A}11 & \quad \forall x (\phi \to \psi) \to (\phi \to \forall x \psi) & \text{where } x \text{ is not free in } \phi \\ \mathrm{A}12 & \quad \forall x (\phi \vee \psi) \to (\phi \vee \forall x \psi) & \text{where } x \text{ is not free in } \phi \end{array} \end{array} $$
  • Logical rules:

    figure a

    It is worth noting that the more familiar form of contraposition (ϕψ) → (¬ψ →¬ϕ) can also be derived. [19, p. 74]

  • Structural rules:

    figure b
  • t-rule:

  • Enthymematic conditional:ϕψ := (ϕt) → ψ

  • Set-theoretic axioms:

    • S1 \( x \in \{z : \phi (z)\} \leftrightarrow \phi (x)\) (abstraction)

    • S2 \( \forall z (z \in x \leftrightarrow z \in y) \leftrightarrow x = y\) (extensionality)

  • Induction axiom:

    Every recursively defined set satisfies induction.

  • Key fact 1: ([19, p. 77])Identity is an equivalence relation.

  • Key fact 2: ([19, p. 77]Sets that differ in membership are non-identical. An important instance of this fact is that ∃(xaxa) → aa, where a is any set.

  • Key fact 3:Footnote 1Where f is some function,

  • Key fact 4: ([19, p. 85]OnOn

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

McAllister, I. Classical Logic is not Uniquely Characterizable. J Philos Logic 51, 1345–1365 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-021-09633-5

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-021-09633-5

Keywords

Navigation