Skip to main content
Log in

Is Aristotelian Naturalism Safe From the Moral Outsider?

  • Published:
Ethical Theory and Moral Practice Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Scott Woodcock has levied a number of objections against Aristotelian naturalism which claims that ethical norms are grounded by reason and biology. His most recent “membership objection” is a synthesis of earlier objections and consists in a trilemma. If Aristotelian naturalists answer the first horn of the trilemma by stipulating that determinations of species-membership are grounded non-empirically, and the second horn of the trilemma by stipulating rationality is species-specific, then they are confronted by a moral outsider—someone who claims that they have non-empirically determined their species membership and are thus guided by different norms of rationality than the rest of us. This permits the moral outsider to act heinously without moral sanction from Aristotelian naturalism. Critics have neglected Alasdair MacIntyre’s Aristotelian naturalism. And he has faced moral-outsider-type counterexamples before. I develop a new response to counterexamples MacIntyre’s account has faced and argue that MacIntyre’s Aristotelian naturalism is able to answer Woodcock’s membership objection. I do this by developing an empirical taxonomy-based approach that enables us to justify the moral outsider’s responsibilities while preserving the best of Aristotelian naturalism.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Availability of data and material (data transparency)

No data used.

Code availability (software application or custom code)

No code used.

Notes

  1. I am grateful to John Hacker-Wright, Scott Woodcock, Jacob Fehr and two anonymous reviewers at this journal for their insightful feedback on drafts of this paper. I am also grateful to Stefan Linquist and Andrew Freundlich for conversations that helped flesh out my views. Finally, I am grateful to the attendees of my presentations of this paper at The University of Guelph and the 14th annual ISME conference.

  2. Interestingly, Kant (1978, 250) acknowledges the possibility of rational moral aliens.

  3. Carson (2014, 38) suggests that MacIntyre provides those with only fragmented and incoherent knowledge of traditions “minimal rational resources.” Given that, for MacIntyre, it is impossible to be rational in any sense without already being part of traditions, it is almost surely the case that those with such resources are already bound by traditional moral norms. I thus discuss this charge only in order to demonstrate what other Aristotelian naturalists can learn from MacIntyre’s theory.

  4. I will note in passing that if the Great Red Dragon is to be rational on MacIntyre’s scheme, he must participate in tradition-constituted enquiry and thus be bound by the virtues of rational independence in addition to the virtues of acknowledged dependence. Whether he participates in such enquiry is something that can be empirically verified, just like membership in the class of intelligent mammals, as neither of these involves species membership.

  5. Following Bergman and Beehner (2015) I define social complexity—which I take to be a measure of how social an animal is—as that which increases with the number of differentiated relationships of individuals. I also take transitive inference ability to be a suitable indicator of intelligence. Studies have demonstrated a positive correlation between transitive inference ability and social complexity (e.g., Maclean et al. 2008).

  6. As Lewens (2020, 483–84) points out, “species” in the sense typically discussed by Aristotelian naturalists shares little in common with empirical accounts. MacIntyre (1999, 22) however appeals to scientific research when characterizing the flourishing of dolphins. This suggests that the MacIntyrian brand of Aristotelian naturalism is friendly to empirical details. Importantly, the empirical account I have outlined avoids the charge of underdetermination Lewens (2020, 486–91) presses against the Aristotelian naturalism of Foot and Thompson.

References

  • Andreou C (2006) Getting on in a Varied World. Soc Theory Practice 32.1:61–73

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle (2001) Nicomachean Ethics. In: McKeon R (ed) Ross W (trans) The Basic Works of Aristotle. Random House, New York, pp 935–1126

    Google Scholar 

  • Bergman T, Beehner J (2015) Measuring Social Complexity. Anim Behav 103:203–209

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carson N (2014) Getting into the Game of Tradition-Constituted Moral Inquiry: Does MacIntyre’s Particularism Offer a Rational Way In? International Philos Q 54(1):25–42

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Copp D, Sobel D (2004) Morality and Virtue: An Assessment of Some Recent Work in Virtue Ethics. Ethics 114.3:514–554

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ereshefsky M (2017) Species. In Zalta E (ed) The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Fall 2017, Stanford, Metaphysics Research Lab, https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2017/entries/species/

  • Foot P (2003) Natural Goodness. Oxford University Press, Online

    Google Scholar 

  • George R (1989) Moral Particularism, Thomism, and Traditions. The Rev of Metaphysics 43.3:593–605

    Google Scholar 

  • Gowans C (2008) Virtue and Nature. Soc Philos Policy 25:1:28–55

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Graham G (2003) MacIntyre on History and Philosophy. In: Murphy M (ed) Alasdair MacIntyre. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 10–37

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacker-Wright J (2009) What Is Natural about Foot’s Ethical. Naturalism? Ratio 22.3:308–321

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harris T (1981) Red Dragon. Dell Publishing, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Herdt J (1998) Alasdair MacIntyre’s ‘Rationality of Traditions’ and Tradition-Transcendental Standards of Justification. The J of Religion 78.4:524–546

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Illies C (2018) Transcendental Aristotelianism: Can the ‘Fresh Start’ of Ethics Find a Happy End? The J of Value Inquiry 52.3:327–346

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jordan J (2017) Philippa Foot’s So-Called Achilles’ Heel: On the Distinctiveness of Her Grammatical Naturalism. American Cathol Philos Q 91.2: 251–271

  • Kant I (1978) Anthropology From a Pragmatic Point of View. Southern Illinois University Press, Carbondale

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewens T (2020) Species Natures: A Critique of Neo-Aristotelian Ethics. The Philos Q 70.280:480–501

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lott M (2002) Reasonably Traditional: Self-Contradiction and Self-Reference in Alasdair MacIntyre’s Account of Tradition-Based Rationality. The J of Relig Ethics 30:3:315–339

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lott M (2012) Moral Virtue as Knowledge of Human Form. Soc Theory and Practice 38.3:407–431

  • Lott M (2014) Why Be a Good Human Being? Natural Goodness, Reason, and the Authority of Human Nature. Philosophia 42.3:761–77

  • Lutz M, Lenman J (2018) Moral Naturalism. In Zalta E (ed) The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Fall 2018, Stanford, Metaphysics Research Lab, https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2018/entries/naturalism-moral/

  • MacIntyre A (1981) After Virtue. University of Notre Dame Press, Notre Dame

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre A (1988) Whose Justice? Which Rationality? University of Notre Dame Press, Notre Dame

  • MacIntyre A (1990a) Aquinas and the Rationality of Tradition. In: Three Rival Versions of Moral Enquiry, University of Notre Dame Press, Notre Dame, pp 127–48

  • MacIntyre A (1990b) Tradition against Encyclopaedia. In: Three Rival Versions of Moral Enquiry, University of Notre Dame Press, Notre Dame, pp 170–95

  • MacIntyre A (1990c) Tradition against Genealogy. In: Three Rival Versions of Moral Enquiry, University of Notre Dame Press, Notre Dame, pp 196–215

  • MacIntyre A (1999) Dependent Rational Animals: Why Human Beings Need the Virtues. Carus Publishing Company, Peru

  • Maclean E, Merritt D, Brannon E (2008) Social complexity predicts transitive reasoning in prosimian primates. Anim Behav 76:479–486

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McCracken, Gennady. (forthcoming) Can a MacIntyrian care about severely disabled strangers? The J of Med and Philos

  • Millgram E (2009) Life and Action. Analysis 69.3:557–564

    Google Scholar 

  • Moosavi P (2020) Natural Goodness without Natural History. Philos Phenomenol Res 0.0:1–23. https://doi.org/10.1111/phpr.12751

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mosteller T (2006) Relativistic Tensions in MacIntyre’s Epistemology. In: Relativism in Contemporary American Philosophy: MacIntyre, Putnam, and Rorty. Continuum, London, pp 45–76

    Google Scholar 

  • Odenbaugh J (2017) Nothing in Ethics Makes Sense except in the Light of Evolution? Natural Goodness, Normativity, and Naturalism. Synthese 194.4:1031–1055. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0675-7

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Seipel P (2014) Tradition-Constituted Inquiry and the Problem of Tradition-Inherence. The Thomist 78.3:419–446

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Seipel P (2015) In Defense of the Rationality of Traditions. Canadian J of Philos 45.3:257–277

  • Thompson M (2008) Life and Action. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson R, Foglia L (2017) Embodied Cognition. In Zalta E (ed) The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Spring 2017, Stanford, Metaphysics Research Lab, https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2017/entries/embodied-cognition/

  • Woodcock S (2006) Philippa Foot’s Virtue Ethics Has an Achilles’ Heel. Dialogue 45.3:445–468

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodcock S (2015) Neo-Aristotelian Naturalism and the Indeterminacy Objection. International J. of Philos Stud. 23.1:20–41

  • Woodcock S (2018) Aristotelian Naturalism vs. Mutants, Aliens and the Great Red Dragon. American Philos Q 55.4:313–328

Download references

Funding

This research was completed while funded under the Philosophy PhD program at the University of Guelph.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Gennady McCracken.

Ethics declarations

Conflicts of interest/Competing interests

No conflicts of interest to disclose.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

McCracken, G. Is Aristotelian Naturalism Safe From the Moral Outsider?. Ethic Theory Moral Prac 24, 1123–1137 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-021-10250-z

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-021-10250-z

Keywords

Navigation