Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-c47g7 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-24T19:14:53.732Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Intertheoretic Relations and the Future of Psychology

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 April 2022

Robert N. McCauley*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, Emory University

Abstract

In the course of defending both a unified model of intertheoretic relations in science and scientific realism, Paul Churchland has attempted to reinvigorate eliminative materialism. Churchland's eliminativism operates on three claims:

(1) that some intertheoretic contexts involve incommensurable theories,

(2) that such contexts invariably require the elimination of one theory or the other, and

(3) that the relation of psychology and neuroscience is just such a context.

I argue that a more detailed account of intertheoretic relations, which distinguishes between the relations that hold between successive theories at a particular level of analysis over time and those that hold between theories at different levels of analysis at the same time, offers grounds for denying Churchland's second and third claims and, therefore, undermines his eliminativism. The paper concludes by suggesting why it is, nonetheless, not unreasonable, given this more detailed model of intertheoretic relations, to expect the eventual elimination of common sense psychology.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Philosophy of Science Association 1986

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

I wish to express my gratitude to Lawrence Barsalou, P. William Bechtel, Alan Donagan, Marshall Gregory, Mark Johnson, Ulric Neisser, William Wimsatt, and Eugene Winograd for their very helpful comments on earlier versions of this paper.

References

Allen, Max (1983), “Models of Hemispheric Specialization”, Psychological Bulletin 93: 73104.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bechtel, P. William (1984), “Autonomous Psychology: What It Should and Should Not Entail” in PSA 1984, Asquith, Peter and Kitcher, Philip (eds.). Volume 1. East Lansing, Michigan: Philosophy of Science Association.Google Scholar
Bechtel, P. William (ed.) (forthcoming), Integrating Scientific Disciplines. Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhoff.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brewer, W. (1974), “There is No Convincing Evidence for Operant or Classical Conditioning in Adult Humans” in Cognition and the Symbolic Processes. Weimer, Walter and Palermo, David (eds.). Hillsdale, New Jersey: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.Google Scholar
Brown, Harold (1979), Preception, Theory and Commitment. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Causey, Robert (1977), Unity of Science. Dordrecht: Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Churchland, Paul (1979), Scientific Realism and the Plasticity of Mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Churchland, Paul (1981), “Eliminative Materialism and the Propositional Attitudes”, Journal of Philosophy 78: 6790.Google Scholar
Churchland, Paul (1984), Matter and Consciousness. Cambridge: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Cornman, James (1962), “The Identity of Mind and Body”, Journal of Philosophy 59: 486–92.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Darden, Lindley, and Maull, Nancy (1977), “Interfield Theories”, Philosophy of Science 44: 4364.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feyerabend, Paul (1962), “Explanation, Reduction, and Empiricism” in Scientific Explanation, Space and Time, Feigl, Herbert and Maxwell, Grover (eds.). Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science. Volume III. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Feyerabend, Paul (1975), Against Method. London: NLB.Google Scholar
Feyerabend, Paul (1978), Science in a Free Society. London: NLB.Google Scholar
Fodor, Jerry (1975), The Language of Thought. New York: Thomas Y. Crowell Company.Google Scholar
Fodor, Jerry (1981), Representations. Cambridge: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Kitcher, Patricia (1984), “In Defense of Intentional Psychology”, Journal of Philosophy 81: 89106.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas (1970), The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Second Edition. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Laudan, Larry (1977), Progress and Its Problems. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press.Google Scholar
McCauley, Robert (1981), “Hypothetical Identities and Ontological Economizing: Comments on Causey's Program for the Unity of Science”, Philosophy of Science 48: 218–27.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McCauley, Robert (1984), “The Not So Happy Story of the Marriage of Linguistics and Psychology”, presented at the Conference on Integrating Scientific Disciplines, Georgia State University. Forthcoming in Synthese.Google Scholar
McCauley, Robert (1986) “Problem Solving in Science and the Competence Approach to Theorizing in Linguistics”. Journal for the Theory of Social Behavior 16: 299313.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McCloskey, Michael (1983), “Intuitive Physics”, Scientific American 248: 122–30.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maull, Nancy (1977), “Unifying Science Without Reduction”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 8: 143–62.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nagel, Ernest (1961), The Structure of Science. New York: Harcourt, Brace, and World.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nickles, Thomas (1973), “Two Concepts of Inter-theoretic Reduction”, Journal of Philosophy 70: 181–201.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Robinson, Joseph (1982), “The Sodium Pump and its Rivals: An Example of Conflict Resolution in Science”, Perspectives in Biology and Medicine 25: 486–95.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rorty, Richard (1965), “Mind-Body Identity, Privacy, and Categories”, Review of Metaphysics 19: 2454.Google Scholar
Rorty, Richard (1970), “Incorrigibility as a Mark of the Mental”, Journal of Philosophy 67: 399424.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rorty, Richard (1979), Philosophy and The Mirror of Nature. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Rorty, Richard (1982), Consequences of Pragmatism. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Schaffner, Kenneth (1967), “Approaches to Reduction”, Philosophy of Science 34: 137–47.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sutherland, N. S. (1970), “Is the Brain a Physical System?” in Explanation in the Behavioural Sciences, Borger, Robert and Cioffi, Frank (eds.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Wimsatt, William (1976a), “Reductionism, Levels of Organization, and the Mind-Body Problem”, in Consciousness and the Brain, Globus, G., Maxwell, G., and Savodnik, I. (eds.). New York: Plenum Press.Google Scholar
Wimsatt, William (1976b), “Reductive Explanation: A Functional Account” in PSA 1974, Cohen, R., Hooker, C., Nicholas, A., and Evra, J. van (eds.). Dordrecht: Reidel.Google Scholar