Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-qsmjn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-23T16:22:47.687Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Moral Rules As Public Goods

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  23 January 2015

Abstract:

The kind of commitment to moral rules that characterizes effective interaction between persons in among others places, manufacturing and commercial settings is characteristically treated by economists and game theorists as a public good, the securing of which requires the expenditure of scarce resources on surveillance and enforcement mechanisms. Alternatively put, the view is that, characteristically, rational persons cannot voluntarily guide their choices by rules, but can only be goaded into acting in accordance with such rules by the fear of social and formal sanctions. On this way of thinking, rational individuals are condemned to having to settle for the “second-best” results that are thereby implied. This conclusion rests not only on an appeal to a consequentialist perspective, but also a separability principle. Against this, it is argued that consequentialism itself offers a basis for the rejection of the separability principle, and a defense of the thesis that, for a wide range of realistic cases, being disposed to voluntarily guide one’s choice by rules (on the condition that others can be expected to do so as well) is a necessary condition of engaging in rational interaction.

Most people do not trust most other people, unmonitored, to honor obligations completely. Because of this they use substantial amounts of resources to specify the details of agreements, and to police them. Use of these resources … could be greatly reduced, if transacting parties would agree to honor the spirit of their agreement and simply shake hands. The resource saving to the two parties combined, from substituting this mode of “enforcing” agreements to those currently used, is clear. Why, then, does not this more efficient mode of transacting drive out the more costly methods through the normal competitive process? … The underlying rationale for this … is that it is privately profitable to engage in some degree of “cheating” on agreements, and to use resources to disguise this fact. — M. W. Reder, “The Place of Ethics in the Theory of Production”

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Society for Business Ethics 1999

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Arrow, K. 1971. “Political and Economic Evaluation of Social Effects and Externalities.” In Intriligator, M., ed., Frontiers of Quantitative Economics. Amsterdam: North-Holland.Google Scholar
Axelrod, R. 1984. The Evolution of Cooperation. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Axelrod, R., and Dion, D. 1988. “The Further Evolution of Cooperation.” Science 242:138590.Google Scholar
Bellman, R. 1954. “The Theory of Dynamic Programming.” Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society 60:503515.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bratman, M. E. 1987. Intention, Plans and Practical Reason. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Buchanan, J., and Tullock, G. 1962. The Calculus of Consent. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.Google Scholar
Calvert, R. 1995a. “The Rational Choice Theory of Social Institutions: Cooperation, Coordination, and Communication.” In Modern Political Economy: Old Topics, New Directions, edited by Banks, J. and Hanushek, E., pp. 216267. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Calvert, R. 1995b. “Rational Actors, Equilibrium, and Social Institutions.” In Explaining Social Institutions, edited by Knight, J. and Sened, I., pp. 5793. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.Google Scholar
Coase, R. 1937. “The Nature of the Firm.” Economica 4:386405.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Coase, R. 1960. “The Problem of Social Cost.” Journal of Law and Economics 3:144CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Danielson, P. 1992. Artificial Morality. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Elster, J. 1979. Ulysses and the Sirens. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Elster, J. 1983. Sour Grapes. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Fudenberg, D. and Tiróle, Jean. 1992. Game Theory. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Gauthier, D. 1986. Morals by Agreement. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Gibbard, A. 1982. “Human Evolution and the Sense of Justice.” Midwest Studies in Philosophy 7 3145.Google Scholar
Kalai, E., and Smorodinsky, M. 1975. “Other Solutions to Nash’s Bargaining Problem.” Econometrica 43:51318.Google Scholar
Kandori, M. 1992. “Social Norms and Community Enforcement.” Review of Economic Studies 59:6380.Google Scholar
Kavka, G. 1983. “The Toxin Puzzle.” Analysis 43:3336.Google Scholar
Luce, R. D., and Raiffa, H. 1957. Games and Decisions. New York: Wiley.Google Scholar
Marwell, G., and Ames, R. E. 1981. “Economists Free Ride, Does Anyone Else?” Journal of Public Economics 15:295310.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McClennen, E. 1988. “Constrained Maximization and Resolute Choice.” Social Philosophy and Policy 5:94118.Google Scholar
McClennen, E. 1989. “Justice and the Problem of Stability.” Philosophy and Public Affairs 18:330.Google Scholar
McClennen, E. 1990a. Rationality and Dynamic Choice: Foundational Explorations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McClennen, E. 1990b. “Foundational Explorations for a Normative Theory of Political Economy.” Constitutional Political Economy 1: 6799.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McClennen, Edward F. 1997. “Pragmatic Rationality and Rules.” Philosophy and Public Affairs 26:210258.Google Scholar
McClennen, Edward F. Forthcoming. “Rethinking Rational Cooperation.” In Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook 5/1997’, edited by Leinfellner, W., et. al. Dordrecht: Kluwer.Google Scholar
Nash, J. F. 1951. “The Bargaining Problem.” Econometrica 21:12840.Google Scholar
Nelson, R. R. 1994. “Evolutionary Theorizing about Economie Change.” In Handbook of Economic Sociology, edited by Smelser, N. and Swedberg, R.Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Parfit, D. 1984. Reasons and Persons. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Rawls, John. 1955. “Two Concepts of Rules.” Philosophical Review 64:332.Google Scholar
Rawls, John. 1971. A Theory of Justice. Cambridge: Belknap Press.Google Scholar
Reder, M. W. 1979. “The Place of Ethics in the Theory of Production.” In Economics and Human Welfare: Essays in Honor of Tibor Scitovsky, edited by Boskin, M. J., pp. 133146. New York: Academic Press.Google Scholar
Sayre McCord, G. 1989. “Deception and Reasons to be Moral.” American Philosophical Quarterly 26:113122.Google Scholar
Schotter, A. 1981. The Economic Theory of Social Institutions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Shapiro, Susan P. 1987. “The Social Control of Personal Trust.” American Journal of Sociology 93:623658.Google Scholar
Smith, Adam. 1776 (1976). An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations. Edited by Campbell, R. H. and Skinner, A. S.Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Strawson, P. F. 1961. “Social Morality and Individual Ideals.” Philosophy 36: 117.Google Scholar
Taylor, M. 1987. The Possibility of Cooperation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Ullmann-Margalit, E. 1977. The Emergence of Norms. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
von Neumann, J. and Morgenstern, O. 1953. Theory of Games and Economic Behavior, Third Edition. New York: Wiley.Google Scholar
Weber, Max. 1923 (1927). General Economic History. Translated by Knight, Frank H.New York: Greenberg.Google Scholar
Weber, Max. 1904–5 (1958). The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism. Translated by Parsons, Talcott. New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons.Google Scholar