Skip to main content
Log in

Irksome assertions

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The Knowledge Account of Assertion (KAA) says that knowledge is the norm of assertion: you may assert a proposition only if you know that it’s true. The primary support for KAA is an explanatory inference from a broad range of linguistic data. The more data that KAA well explains, the stronger the case for it, and the more difficult it is for the competition to keep pace. In this paper we critically assess a purported new linguistic datum, which, it has been argued, KAA well explains. We argue that KAA does not well explain it.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Competing accounts of assertion include the Truth Account, which says truth is the norm of assertion (Weiner 2005), the Belief Account, which says belief is the norm of assertion (Bach 2008), and the Reasonable Belief Account, which says that reasonable belief is the norm of assertion (Kvanvig 2009; relatedly, Douven 2006; Lackey 2007; McKinnon 2012), and the Certainty Account, which says that certainty is the norm of assertion (Stanley 2008).

  2. At least, it does not do so as easily as ‘I believe’ does. More on this below.

  3. We are ambivalent about whether this sentence should end with a question mark or a period.

  4. An anonymous referee asks whether Benton might take a cue from Blaauw (2012), who points out that the parenthetical ‘I know’ can be used to ‘reinforce’ an unadorned assertion that P by upgrading it to a claim to know that P. Perhaps, the referee suggests, the parenthetical ‘I ask’ or ‘I’m curious’ or ‘I say’ can also ‘serve to reinforce the main claim of the sentence in question.’ We tend to doubt that this suggestion will work, for two reasons. First, interrogatives don’t make claims, so there is no claim for ‘I ask’ or ‘I’m curious’ to reinforce. Second, ‘I say’ typically functions as a hedge, not as a reinforcement in Blaauw’s sense. (Blaauw 2012: 107 makes essentially the same point about ‘I believe’.) We do agree that ‘I say’ or ‘I claim’, ‘I ask’, etc., can add rhetorical emphasis, but this is not the same as reinforcement in Blaauw’s sense. And as we explain in the main text below, there will always be ways to modify the context so that adding a parenthetical is non-redundant, but this isn’t enough for Benton’s purposes.

References

  • Bach, K. (2008). Applying pragmatics to epistemology. Philosophical Issues, 18, 68–88.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Benton, M. (2011). Two more for the knowledge account of assertion. Analysis, 71(4), 684–687.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blaauw, M. (2012). Reinforcing the knowledge account of assertion. Analysis, 72(1), 105–108.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DeRose, K. (2002). Assertion, knowledge, and context. Philosophical Review, 111(2), 167–203.

    Google Scholar 

  • DeRose, K. (2009). The case for contextualism: Knowledge, skepticism and context (Vol. 1). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Douven, I. (2006). Assertion, knowledge and rational credibility. Philosophical Review, 115(4), 449–485.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kvanvig, J. L. (2009). Assertion, knowledge, and lotteries. In D. Pritchard & P. Greenough (Eds.), Williamson on knowledge, pp. 140–160.

  • Lackey, J. (2007). Norms of assertion. Noûs, 41(4), 594–626.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKinnon, R. (2012). How do you know that ‘how do you know?’ Challenges a speaker’s knowledge? Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 93, 65–83.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moore, G. E. (1942). A reply to my critics. In P. Schilpp (Ed.), The philosophy of G.E. Moore. La Salle, IL: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, G. E. (1962). Commonplace book: 1919–1953. London: Allen and Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sorensen, R. (1988). Blindspots. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stanley, J. (2008). Knowledge and certainty. Philosophical Issues, 18, 33–55.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Turri, J. (2010). Prompting challenges. Analysis, 70(3), 456–462.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Turri, J. (2011). The express knowledge account of assertion. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 89(1), 37–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Unger, P. (1975). Ignorance: A case for skepticism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weiner, M. (2005). Must we know what we say? Philosophical Review, 114(2), 227–251.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2000). Knowledge and its limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

For helpful feedback and conversation, we thank Matt Benton, Tim Kenyon and Angelo Turri. This research was kindly supported by the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada, the British Academy/Association of Commonwealth Universities, the National Endowment for the Humanities, and an Ontario Early Researcher Award.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to John Turri.

Additional information

The authors contributed equally and are listed alphabetically.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

McKinnon, R., Turri, J. Irksome assertions. Philos Stud 166, 123–128 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-012-0028-z

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-012-0028-z

Keywords

Navigation