Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-wg55d Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-03T01:33:43.486Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Van Fraassen's Unappreciated Realism

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2022

Abstract

What is not often noted about Bas van Fraassen's distinctive approach to the scientific realism issue is that constructive empiricism, as he defines it, seems to involve a distinctively realist stance in regard to large parts of natural science. This apparent defection from the ranks of his more uncompromisingly anti-realist colleagues raises many questions. Is he really leaning to realism here? If he is, why is this not more widely noted? And, more important, if he is, is he entitled to this shyly realist concession? Does his many-pronged attack on what he sees as the main arguments in support of realism leave him with the wherewithal?

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

This paper recalls one of the issues debated between Ernan McMullin and Bas van Fraassen on two earlier occasions: first, during the course of the annual Cardinal Mercier Lectures at the Catholic University of Leuven (Belgium) given by Ernan McMullin, and then during the annual Cuming Lectures at University College Dublin which took the form of an extended discussion between McMullin and van Fraassen on the more general theme: “Realism and anti-realism in the philosophy of science.” The author wishes to express his gratitude to his hosts on both those occasions: Professor Carlos Steel (Higher Institute of Philosophy, Leuven), and Professor Dermot Moran (Dublin).

References

Duhem, Pierre (1969), To Save the Appearances. Translated by Doland, E. and Maschler, C.. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Hacking, Ian (1983), Representing and Intervening. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hacking, Ian (1985), “Do We See Through a Microscope?”, in Churchland, Paul and Hooker, Clifford (eds.), Images of Science. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 132152.Google Scholar
Hacking, Ian (1989), “Extragalactic Reality: The Case of Gravitational Leasing”, Extragalactic Reality: The Case of Gravitational Leasing 56:555581.Google Scholar
Harman, Gilbert (1965), “The Inference to the Best Explanation”, The Inference to the Best Explanation 74:8895.Google Scholar
Harman, Gilbert (1968), “Knowledge, Inference, and Explanation”, Knowledge, Inference, and Explanation 5:164173.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas (1971), The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. 2d ed. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas (1977), “Objectivity, Value-Judgement and Theory Choice”, in his The Essential Tension, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 320338.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ladyman, James, et al. (1997), “A Defence of van Fraassen’s Critique of Abductive Inference”, A Defence of van Fraassen’s Critique of Abductive Inference 47:305321.Google Scholar
Laudan, Larry (1984), “A Confutation of Convergent Realism”, in Leplin, Jarrett (ed.), Scientific Realism. Berkeley: University of California Press, 218249.Google Scholar
Laudan, Rachel (1987), From Mineralogy to Geology: The Foundations of a Science, 1650–1830. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leplin, Jarrett (1997), A Novel Defense of Scientific Realism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
McMullin, Ernan (1975), “The Conception of Science in Galileo’s Work”, in Butts, Robert E. and Pitt, Joseph C. (eds.), New Perspectives on Galileo. Dordrecht: Reidel, 209257.Google Scholar
McMullin, Ernan (1983), “Values in Science”, in Asquith, Peter and Nickles, Tom (eds.), PSA 1982. E. Lansing, MI: Philosophy of Science Association, 325.Google Scholar
McMullin, Ernan (1984a), “A Case of Scientific Realism”, in Leplin, Jarrett (ed.), Scientific Realism. Berkeley: University of California Press, 840.Google Scholar
McMullin, Ernan (1984b), “The Goals of Natural Science”, The Goals of Natural Science 58:3764.Google Scholar
McMullin, Ernan (1992), The Inference That Makes Science. Milwaukee: Marquette University Press.Google Scholar
McMullin, Ernan (1993), “Rationality and Paradigm-change in Science”, in Horwich, Paul (ed.), World Changes: Thomas Kuhn and the Nature of Science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 5578.Google Scholar
McMullin, Ernan (1996a), “Enlarging Imagination”, Enlarging Imagination 58:227260.Google Scholar
McMullin, Ernan (1996b), “Epistemic Virtue and Theory-Apprasial”, in Douven, Igor and Hursten, Leon (eds.), Realism and the Sciences. Leuven: Leuven University Press, 134.Google Scholar
McMullin, Ernan (2000), “Truth and Explanatory Success in Aristotle”, in Sfendoni-Mentzov, D. (ed.), Aristotle and Contemporary Science. New York: Peter Lang, 6071.Google Scholar
McMullin, Ernan (2002), “The Origins of the Field Concept in Physics”, Physics in Perspective, in press.Google Scholar
Psillos, Stathis (1996), “On van Fraassen’s Critique of Abductive Reasoning”, On van Fraassen’s Critique of Abductive Reasoning 46:3147.Google Scholar
Psillos, Stathis (1999), Scientific Realism: How Science Tracks Truth. London: Routledge, 1999.Google Scholar
Rosen, Gideon (1996), “Constructive Empiricism”, Constructive Empiricism 74:143178.Google Scholar
van Fraassen, Bas (1980), The Scientific Image. Oxford: Clarendon.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van Fraassen, Bas (1985), “Empiricism in the Philosophy of Science”, in Churchland, Paul and Hooker, Clifford (eds.), Images of Science. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 245308.Google Scholar
van Fraassen, Bas (1989), Laws and Symmetry. Oxford: Clarendon, 1989.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van Fraassen, Bas (1994), “Gideon Rosen on Constructive Empiricism”, Gideon Rosen on Constructive Empiricism 74:179192.Google Scholar