Skip to main content
Log in

Against quietist normative realism

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Recently, some philosophers have suggested that a form of robust realism about ethics, or normativity more generally, does not face a significant explanatory burden in metaphysics. I call this view metaphysically quietist normative realism. This paper argues that while this view can appear to constitute an attractive alternative to more traditional forms of normative realism, it cannot deliver on this promise. I examine Scanlon’s attempt to defend such a quietist realism, and argue that rather than silencing metaphysical questions about normative reasons, his defense at best succeeds only in shifting the focus of metaphysical enquiry. I then set aside the details of Scanlon’s view, and argue on general grounds that that the quietist realist cannot finesse a crucial metanormative task: to explain the contrast between the correct normative system and alternative putatively normative standards.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. I take the term ‘metanormative’ from Enoch 2007. Compare Hussain 2004, pp. 150–151 for a slightly different interpretation of the central project.

  2. I oversimplify: one might (à la Quine) reject an ontology of facts on general grounds, but nonetheless remain a realist about some domains. I set aside this complication.

  3. Besides Scanlon, who will be my central exemplar of this view in Sect. 2, philosophers who have made remarks that may be suggestive of such a view include Parfit forthcoming Part Six., Nagel 1997, and Dworkin 1996. The interpretation of the relevant aspects of each of these authors’ work is difficult and controversial. On Dworkin, compare Zangwill 1996 and Dworkin’s 1997 response. Svavarsdottir 2001 is an extremely helpful exploration of Nagel’s views on these topics. For an important related view, see Kramer 2009.

  4. Leading examples of metanormative or more narrowly metaethical naturalist realists include Boyd 1997, Railton 1997, Smith 1994, Jackson and Pettit 1995, Schroeder 2007.

  5. Complaints of this kind directed at specific naturalist accounts of ethics and epistemology are ubiquitous. Parfit’s “Appendix A: Normativity Naturalism, and Non-Cognitivism.” (Ms. of June 2008) offers an unusually strong general version of this charge against the naturalist.

  6. This view is raised as a serious possibility by Copp 2004 and defended by Tiffany 2007.

  7. Helpful discussions of the idea of direction of fit sketched here include Humberstone 1992 and Velleman 1992.

  8. See for example Gibbard 2003, and especially Blackburn 1993.

  9. It is not trivial to spell out this idea once one accepts minimalism. See Dreier 2005 for a helpful discussion. Quasi-realism should be distinguished from the sort of view that a normative realist might have if she found the expressivist treatment of the distinctive normativity of practical discourse compelling, and sought to graft that account onto a realist framework (for attempts at such grafting for different purposes, see Copp 2001 and Finlay 2007). Quietist realists show no signs of seeking to deploy such a strategy, so I set it aside here.

  10. Compare Moore 1903, Shafer-Landau 2003, and Fitzpatrick 2008, among many others.

  11. The classic statement of this charge comes in the papers reprinted as Chaps. 6 and 7 in Blackburn’s 1993. For an important recent response, see Sects. 8–11 of Fitzpatrick 2008.

  12. The term ‘mysterianism’ is most commonly used in the philosophy of mind, to label the view that the relationship between experiential states and underlying physical causes necessarily eludes our epistemic grasp (compare McGinn 1993 and Stoljar 2006, pp. 91–92).

  13. For example, this is one thread of Korsgaard’s critique of ‘substantive moral realists’: she concludes that such realism “… refuses to answer the normative question. It is a way of saying that it cannot be done” (1996, p. 39).

  14. For a more detailed discussion of the distinction between metaethics and normative ethics see McPherson 2008a, Chap. 1. For worries about the distinction between metaethics and normative ethics see Kagan 1998, Dworkin 1996, and Korsgaard 2003.

  15. For further discussion of a strong version of such justificatory autonomy in ethics, see McPherson 2008b.

  16. Scanlon glosses natural facts as including “…all and only the physical and (insofar as they may be different) psychological facts” (2003, p. 8). He also suggests the different idea that the natural world is just the world as described by science. The distinction between natural and non-natural properties is actually quite vexing. I set aside the very real interpretive issues here, which are orthogonal to the argument of this section.

  17. As we noted in Sect. 1, non-naturalism is often taken to make the demand for metaphysical explanation especially intense. This is in part because the non-naturalist claims that the sorts of properties that explain normativity are different in kind from the sorts of properties identified by the sciences. Scanlon argues that on his conception, reasons do not conflict with the picture of the world offered by science because plausible claims about reasons do not entail predictions about the spatiotemporal world that might conflict with those generated by scientific theories (2003, pp. 7–9). This response assumes (implausibly, it seems to me,) that the ‘picture of the world’ offered by contemporary science is limited to specific positive ontological claims made by scientific theories, and does not involve more general commitments concerning what kinds of things exist. I set this concern aside here.

  18. 1998, p. 57. One might worry over whether we should let propositions into our ontology, and hence whether, on the propositional account of reasons-talk, we should admit reasons. For reasons that will become clear immediately below, I set this concern aside.

  19. Scanlon himself notes that the ‘element of normative force’ does not adhere to propositions themselves, but rather to judgments that if a proposition were true, it would be a good reason for a certain action or belief (1998, p. 57).

  20. A similar point is briefly made by Finlay 2007, p. 840. Compare also Olson’s related 2009, Sect. 3 discussion of what he calls the ‘extensional fallacy’.

  21. Scanlon takes this language from Wright 1996, p. 5. One might worry that this appeal undermines Scanlon’s realist pretensions. Roughly, Wright suggests that we might earn the right to talk of truth and falsehood within a domain of discourse in virtue of the internal discipline of the discourse, rather than by appealing to a more ‘metaphysical’ basis for the truth of such claims. Wright conceives of this denial of ‘metaphysical gravitas’ as anti-realist in an important sense, and with good reason: there is nothing in the idea of an internally disciplined discourse that suggests that there couldn’t be a variety of inconsistent but equally disciplined discourses, which our deliberative practices might just as easily have instantiated.

  22. I take it that Scanlon’s commitment to the idea that standards for correct reasoning are fundamental helps to explain his otherwise surprising claim that his view is, in Korsgaard’s (1996, pp. 34–37) terms, a form of ‘procedural’ as opposed to ‘substantive’ realism (Scanlon 1998, p. 380, n. 48). However, Scanlon’s discussion of Korsgaard in 2003, pp. 13–15 suggests that he may no longer want to characterize his view in this way.

  23. Such evidence would be deeply peculiar in virtue of being self-undermining: if one had it, one could not coherently treat it as evidence. However, since one can have evidence that one does not recognize as such, this peculiarity does not undermine the force of the objection.

  24. For example, Jackson and Pettit 1995 offer a holistic account of moral semantics that they conjoin with a naturalistic metaphysics of morality.

  25. Compare Copp 2004’s similar (but slightly narrower) notion of generic normativity, and Foot 1972 on the normativity of etiquette. I set aside the other central dimension of chess normativity, which is illustrated by the fact that it is possible to play a legal but bad move.

  26. Here and below, I talk for the sake of brevity as if Scanlon is correct that reasons are the fundamental normative notions. Nothing hangs on this: for example my argument could be translated without loss into a discussion of values, virtues or standards for reasoning.

  27. The language here is inspired by Enoch’s “Agency, Schmagency…” (2006). However, I am pursuing a different point with the contrast than Enoch is with his.

  28. Again, the deflationary naturalism defended by Tiffany (2007) denies this asymmetry.

  29. Parfit MS Sect. 15 goes so far as to suggest that naturalist realists simply could not be talking about the same sort of thing that he is interested in when he makes normative claims, because such views cannot coherently explain the robust normativity of normative properties.

  30. It is notable that Moore’s 1903, Sect. 13 complaint about the second-order desire view as an analysis of goodness appears to focus entirely on the intuitive case against synonymy. Contemporary opponents of naturalism have tended to abandon the conceptual interpretation of the open question argument as insufficient. An especially clear example is Rosati 1995, which suggests that the open question argument can be resuscitated exactly by focusing on the alleged intuitive inadequacy of naturalist attempts to explain normative authority.

  31. Consider two examples of such a metaphysical explanation. According to the reductive second-order desire theory of reasons, to be robustly normative just is to be properly related to a second-order desire. By contrast, the traditional non-naturalist insists that robust normativity is a sui generis metaphysical property. On either of these views, the explanation of the contrast between reasons and schmeasons is made by appeal to the metaphysical nature of normative properties, and is thus inconsistent with quietist realism.

  32. I am grateful to Sari Kisilevsky for pressing this line of objection.

  33. This claim has been explicitly made across the history of discussions of metaethics and normative ethics. For example, compare Frankena 1951, p. 45, Zimmerman 1980, p. 659, and Kagan 1998, p. 5 (Kagan does not explicitly endorse this claim). Sumner 1967, 96ff shows how a stronger version of this sort of claim has sometimes motivated the thought that metaethics must be ‘normatively neutral’.

  34. I oversimplify: the metanormative theory would also need to preserve the structure of the correct normative theory. So if the correct normative theory were a virtue theory, then on this theory to be a virtue would be to be a character trait hated by Hades, and Hades would need to hate actions because they expressed virtue, etc. The task of filling out the simplified story given in the text is structurally analogous to the task of developing an intuitively extensionally adequate Divine Command metaethic.

  35. Compare the use of rigidification in Dreier 2002 to make a similar point about possible metanormative theories whose content outruns their normative implications.

  36. Against the attempt to resurrect quietism in a Kantian key, it is relevant that similar problems have been raised about Korsgaard’s theory: for example, Hussain and Shah ms. have argued that Korsgaard’s theory is compatible with either realist or expressivist metaethics, thus suggesting that her view is compatible with either a metaphysical or psychological account of normativity. Korsgaard’s best hope of avoiding this problem is to defend the view mentioned above that the debate between metanormative realists and anti-realists rests on a mistaken understanding of the issues (for which compare her 2003). Besides being deeply problematic (see Hussain and Shah ms. and 2006, and McPherson 2008b), this strategy is unavailable to the quietist realist, who is an antagonist in the realism-antirealism debate.

  37. Thanks to David Enoch for pressing this objection on the quietist’s behalf.

  38. In the enormously helpful terms of Schroeder 2005, the divine command theorist offers a constitutive explanation.

  39. For example, Yalom 2004, p. 18 suggests that when chess was introduced to Europe from the Arab world in the Middle Ages, the rules were modified so that it was illegal to promote a pawn to a queen while one still possessed another queen. Yalom suggests that this change was made to avoid the appearance that the game condoned polygamy. While this change has since been reversed, I take it that instances of this sort of pattern of explanation of the rules of chess would in no way undermine the validity of those rules.

References

  • Blackburn, S. (1993). Essays in quasi-realism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R. (1997). How to be a moral realist. In S. Darwall, A. Gibbard & P. Railton (Eds.), Moral discourse and practice (pp. 105–136). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Copp, D. (2001). Realist-expressivism: A neglected option for moral realism. Social Philosophy and Policy, 18, 1–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Copp, D. (2004). Moral naturalism and three grades of normativity. In P. Schaber (Ed.), Normativity and naturalism (pp. 7–45). Frankfurt: Ontos-Verlag.

  • Darwall, S., Gibbard, A., & Railton, P. (Eds.). (1997). Moral discourse and practice. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreier, J. (2002) Metaethics and normative commitment. Philosophical Issues, 12, 241–263 (In E. Sosa & E. Villanueva (Eds.), Realism and relativism).

  • Dreier, J. (2005). Metaethics and the problem of creeping minimalism. Philosophical Perspectives, 18 (Ethics), 23–44.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, R. (1996). Objectivity and truth: You’d better believe it. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 25(2), 87–139.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, R. (1997). Replies to critics: Zangwill. In J. Dreier, & D. Estlund (Eds.), Brown electronic article review service. Posted 4/9/1997. Available at: http://www.brown.edu/Departments/Philosophy/bears/homepage.html.

  • Enoch, D. (2006). Agency, shmagency: Why normativity won’t come from what is constitutive of action. Philosophical Review, 115(2), 169–198.

    Google Scholar 

  • Enoch, D. (2007). An outline of an argument for robust metanormative realism. In R. Shafer-Landau (Ed.), Oxford studies in metaethics (Vol. 2, pp. 21–50). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Finlay, S. (2007). Four faces of moral realism. Philosophy Compass, 2(6), 820–849.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fitzpatrick, W. (2008). Robust ethical realism, non-naturalism and normativity. In R. Shafer-Landau (Ed.), Oxford studies in metaethics (Vol. 3). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foot, P. (1972). Morality as a system of hypothetical imperatives. Philosophical Review, 81(3), 305–316.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frankena, W. K. (1951). Main trends in recent philosophy: Moral philosophy at mid-century. Philosophical Review, 69(1), 44–55.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibbard, A. (2003). Thinking how to live. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Humberstone, I. L. (1992). Direction of fit. Mind, 101(401), 59–84.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hussain, N. (2004). The return of moral fictionalism. Philosophical Perspectives, 18, 149–187.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hussain, N., & Nishi Shah. (ms.). Metaethics and its discontents: A case study in Korsgaard. Ms. version 2.2.

  • Hussain, N., & Nishi Shah. (2006). Misunderstanding metaethics: Korsgaard’s rejection of realism. In Russ Shafer-Landau (Ed.), Oxford studies in metaethics (Vol. 1, pp. 265–294). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F., & Pettit, P. (1995). Moral functionalism and moral motivation. Philosophical Quarterly, 45(178), 20–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kagan, S. (1998). Normative ethics. Boulder, CO: Westview.

    Google Scholar 

  • Korsgaard, C. (1996). The sources of normativity. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Korsgaard, C. (2003). Realism and constructivism in twentieth-century moral philosophy. Journal of Philosophical Research, APA Centennial Supp. Philosophy in America at the Turn of the Century, 99–122.

  • Kramer, M. (2009). Moral realism as a moral doctrine. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mackie, J. L. (1977). Ethics: Inventing right and wrong. Harmondsworth: Penguin.

  • McGinn, C. (1993). The problem of consciousness: Essays towards a resolution. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • McPherson, T. (2008a). For unity in moral theorizing. Princeton University Dissertation, 2008. Available at www.d.umn.edu/∼tristram/research.

  • McPherson, T. (2008b). Metaethics and the autonomy of morality. Philosophers’ Imprint 08.06, 1–16. www.philosophersimprint.org/008006/.

  • Moore, G. E. (1903). Principia Ethica. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, T. (1997). The last word. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Olson, J. (2009). Reasons and the new non-naturalism. In S. Robertson (Ed.), Spheres of reason (pp. 164–182). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, D. (forthcoming). On what matters. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Railton, P. (1997). Moral realism. In Darwall, Gibbard, & Railton (Eds.), (pp. 137–163). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Rosati, C. (1995). Naturalism, normativity, and the open question argument. Nous, 29(1), 46–70.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scanlon, T. (1998). What we owe to each other. Cambridge, MA: Belknap.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scanlon, T. (2003). Metaphysics and morals. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 77(2), 7–22.

  • Schroeder, M. (2005). Cudworth and normative explanations. Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy, 1(3), 1–27.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schroeder, M. (2007). Slaves of the passions. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Shafer-Landau, R. (2003). Moral realism: A defence. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, M. (1994). The moral problem. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stoljar, D. (2006). Ignorance and imagination. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sumner, L. W. (1967). Normative ethics and metaethics. Ethics, 77(2), 95–106.

    Google Scholar 

  • Svavarsdottir, S. (2001). Objective values: Does metaethics rest on a mistake? In B. Leiter (Ed.), Objectivity in law and morals (pp. 144–193). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tiffany, E. (2007). Deflationary normative pluralism. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 33(Suppl [vol. 33]), 231–262.

    Google Scholar 

  • Velleman, J. D. (1992). The guise of the good. Noûs, 26(1), 3–26.

  • Wright, C. (1996). Truth in ethics. In B. Hooker (Ed.), Truth in ethics (pp. 1–18). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yalom, M. (2004). Birth of the chess queen. New York: Harper Collins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zangwill, N. (1996). Comments on Dworkin. In J. Dreier & D. Estlund (Eds.), Brown Electronic Article Review Service. Posted 12/2/1996. Available at: http://www.brown.edu/Departments/Philosophy/bears/homepage.html.

  • Zimmerman, D. (1980). Meta-ethics naturalized. Canadian Journal of Philosophy X(4), 637–662.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Tristram McPherson.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

McPherson, T. Against quietist normative realism. Philos Stud 154, 223–240 (2011). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-010-9535-y

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-010-9535-y

Keywords

Navigation