Skip to main content
Log in

Did Descartes make a Diagonal Argument?

  • Published:
Journal of Philosophical Logic Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper explores the idea that Descartes’ cogito is a kind of diagonal argument. Using tools from modal logic, it reviews some historical antecedents of this idea from Slezak and Boos and culminates in an orginal result classifying the exact structure of belief frames capable of supporting diagonal arguments and our reconstruction of the cogito.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  1. George Boolos. The Logic of Provability. Cambridge University Press (1993).

  2. Boos, W. (1983). A self-referential ’cogito’. Philosophical Studies, 44(2), 269–290.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  3. Descartes, R., & Maclean, I. (2006). A Discourse on the Method. Oxford World’s Classics. UK: Oxford university press.

  4. Descartes, R., Cottingham, J., & Williams, B. (1996). Meditations on First Philosophy: With Selections From the Objections and Replies. Cambridge University Press.

  5. Field, H. (2008). Saving truth from paradox. Oxford: OUP.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  6. Fine, K. (1970). Propositional Quantifiers in Modal Logic. Theoria, 36(3):336–346.

  7. Gupta, A., & Belnap, N. (1993). The revision theory of truth. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  8. Hintikka, J. (1962). Cogito, ergo sum: Inference or performance. Philosophical Review, 71(1), 3–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  9. Kripke, S. (1975). Outline of a theory of truth. Journal of Philosophy, 72, 690–716.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  10. Leitgeb, H. (2008). Towards a logic of type-free modality and truth. In C. Dimitracopoulos et al. (Eds.) Logic Colloquium 05, Lecture Notes in Logic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  11. Montague, R. (1963). Syntactical treatments of modality. Acta Philosophica Fennica, 16, 153–167.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Prawitz, D. (1967). Completeness and hauptsatz for second order logic. Theoria, 33(3), 246–258.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  13. Priest, G. (1979). The logic of paradox. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 8, 219–241.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  14. Priest, G. (2008). An Introduction to Non-Classical Logic: From if to is. Melbourne: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  15. Slezak, P. (1983). Descartes’s diagonal deduction. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 34, 13–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  16. Slezak, P. (1988). Was descartes a liar? diagonal doubt defended. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 39(3), 379–388.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  17. Slezak, P. (2010). Doubts about indubitability. Philosophical Forum, 41(4), 389–412.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  18. Smullyan, R.M. (1968). First-Order logic. New York: Dover.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  19. Sorensen, R.A. (1986). Was descartes’s cogito a diagonal deduction. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 37(3), 346–351.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  20. Tarski, A. (1944). The semantical conception of truth: and the foundations of semantics. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 4(3), 341–376.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  21. Tarski, A. (1956). The concept of truth in formalized languages. In J. Corcoran (Ed.) Logic, semantics, metamathematics: papers from 1923 to 1938. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

  22. Toledo, S. (1975). Tableau systems for first order numbers theory and certain higher order theories. Berlin: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  23. Williamson, T. (2000). Knowledge and its Limits. Oxford University Press.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Toby Meadows.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

I’d like to thank Fabio Lampert, Luca Moretti, Stephen Read and Zach Weber for their valuable thoughts and advice.

Appendix

Appendix

Theorem

(4) Let \({\mathscr{M}}=\langle W,R,v\rangle \) be a model of propositional modal logic. Then the following are equivalent:

  1. 1.

    Player II has a well-aligned winning strategy in the diagonal game for \({\mathscr{M}}\); and

  2. 2.

    There is a diagonal proposition on \({\mathscr{M}}\): i.e., there is some proposition p such that \({\mathscr{M}}\models p\leftrightarrow \neg \Box p\).

Remark Note also that this is crucially distinct from saying that \({\mathscr{M}}\models \exists p(p\leftrightarrow \neg \Box p)\). This latter formulation merely demands that at every world there is some proposition which is true if and only if it is doubted and nothing about its behaviour at other worlds. We rather want a proposition p which upholds \({\mathscr{M}}\models p\leftrightarrow \neg \Box p\) thus vindicating our intention that p just means that I doubt p. remark

Proof

(2)→(1) Let p be such that for all wW \(w\Vdash p\leftrightarrow \neg \Box p\). We construct a strategy for II as follows.

I’s first move can be anywhere in W, so for all wW we let:

$$ \sigma(w)=\begin{cases} \text{pass} & \text{if }w\Vdash\Box p\\ \text{some }u\text{ s.t. }u\Vdash\Box p\text{ and }wRu & \text{if }w\Vdash\neg\Box p. \end{cases} $$

Now suppose \(\bar {w}=\langle w_{0},...,w_{2n}\rangle \) be a partial play following σ in which I has played last. Then we let

$$ \sigma(\bar{w})=\text{some }u\text{ s.t. }u\Vdash\Box p\text{ and }w_{2n}Ru. $$

The following claim establishes that there is no way of stopping this construction.

Claim

σ is well defined.

Proof

Suppose not. Then let \(\bar {w}\) be a play of least length such that I made the last move and \(\sigma (\bar {w})\) is not defined. Suppose n = 0. Then \(\bar {w}=\langle w_{0}\rangle \). If \(w_{0}\Vdash \Box p\), then II can pass. If \(w_{0}\nVdash \Box p\), then \(w_{0}\Vdash \neg \Box p\) and so there is some uW with w0Ru and \(u\Vdash \neg p\). Thus II can play such a u and we’ll have \(u\Vdash \Box p\).

Suppose n > 0. Then \(\bar {w}=\langle w_{0},...,w_{2n}\rangle \) for some n > 0. Since \(\sigma (\bar {w})\) is not defined, there is no u such that w2nRu and \(u\Vdash \Box p\). Suppose \(w_{2n}\Vdash \neg \Box p\), then for some u with w2nRu we have \(u\Vdash \neg p\) and so \(u\Vdash \Box p\): contradiction. Thus \(w_{2n}\Vdash \Box p\) and so \(w_{2n}\Vdash \neg p\). But the by the minimality of \(\bar {w}\) we see that II’s earlier moves are well-defined and so we must have \(w_{2n-1}\Vdash \Box p\) and so \(w_{2n}\Vdash p\): contradiction. □

The following lemma is useful below:

Lemma

Let \(\bar {w}\) be a partial play of the diagonal game played in accordance with σ for II. Then □-assigned (¬□-assigned) worlds w are such that \(w\Vdash \Box p\) (\(w\Vdash \neg \Box p\)).

Proof

Let \(\bar {w}\) be a play of minimal length n such that this fails. Suppose n = 0. Then \(\bar {w}=\langle w_{0}\rangle \). Suppose II passes using σ. Then w0 is □-assigned by definition and \(w_{0}\Vdash \Box p\) by the definition of σ. Suppose II doesn’t pass using σ. Then w0 is ¬□-assigned and \(w_{0}\Vdash \neg \Box p\) according to σ.

Suppose \(\bar {w}=\langle w_{0},...,w_{2n}\rangle \) for some n > 0; i.e., I played last. Then we see that w2n− 1Rw2n, \(w_{2n-1}\Vdash \Box p\) by minimality, while \(w_{2n}\Vdash \Box p\). But then we have \(w_{2n}\Vdash p\) and \(w_{2n}\Vdash \neg p\): contradiction. Suppose \(\bar {w}=\langle w_{0},...,w_{2n+1}\rangle \) for some n > 0; i.e., II played last. Then by definition of σ, \(w_{2n+1}\Vdash \Box p\) as required. □

Claim

σ is a winning strategy for II.

Proof

Suppose not. Then there is some play \(\bar {w}=\langle w_{0},...,w_{2n}\rangle \) of minimal length such that II has already lost or cannot legally move at this point. Suppose n = 0. Then \(\bar {w}=\langle w_{0}\rangle \). Suppose \(w_{0}\Vdash \Box p\) so w0 is □-assigned. Then II legally passes and so has not lost. Suppose \(w_{0}\Vdash \neg \Box p\) so w0 is ¬□-assigned. Then we may fix u with w0Ru such that \(u\Vdash \neg p\). Thus \(u\Vdash \Box p\) and w0 is □-assigned. Since there are no earlier moves and I’s move was appropriated, there is no way for II to lose at this point by playing u.

Suppose n > 0. Then for all all u we have either:

  1. (1)

    ¬w2nRu; or

  2. (2)

    one of the following holds:

    1. (a)

      there is a ¬□-assigned w in \(\bar {w}\) such that w = u;

    2. (b)

      there is a □-assigned world w in \(\bar {w}\) such that wRu; or

    3. (c)

      there is a □-assigned world w in \(\bar {w}\) such that w = w2n.

Since w2n is ¬□-assigned, we see that \(w_{2n}\Vdash \neg \Box p\), and so we may fix we make fix some u such that w2nRu and \(u\Vdash \neg p\). Now suppose that either (a), (b) or (c) are true.

(a) Fix w a ¬□-assigned world in \(\bar {w}\) and suppose w = u. Then we have \(w\Vdash \neg \Box p\) and \(u=w\Vdash p\): contradiction.

(b) Fix w a □-assigned world in \(\bar {w}\) and suppose wRu. Then since \(w\Vdash \Box p\), we have \(u\Vdash p\): contradiction.

(c) Fix w a □-assigned world in \(\bar {w}\) and suppose w = w2n. Then since \(w\Vdash \Box p\) and \(w_{2n}\Vdash \neg \Box p\): contradiction. □

Finally, it can be seen that σ is such that all and only the worlds w such that \(p\Vdash \Box p\) are played (or appropriated) by II; i.e., the □-assigned worlds. Thus σ is well-aligned.

(1)→(2)Suppose II has a well-aligned winning strategy σ for II in \({\mathscr{M}}\). Let p be such that for all wW

$$ w\Vdash p\ \Leftrightarrow\ w\text{ is }\neg\Box\text{-assigned in every play compatible with }\sigma. $$

Suppose \(w_{0}\Vdash p\). So w0 is ¬□-assigned in all plays compatible with σ. Suppose for a contradiction that \(w_{0}\Vdash \Box p\). Then for all w1 with w0Rw1 we have \(w_{1}\Vdash p\) and w1 is ¬□-assigned (by the assignment above). Given that w0 is ¬□-assigned, it can be seen through the definition that w0 must have been played by I. Suppose there is some w1 such that w0Rw1. Then we see that no matter how II plays after w0, we end up with a play containing consecutive worlds which are both ¬□-assigned: contradicting the well-alignment of σ. Suppose there is no w1 such that w0Rw1; i.e., w0 is a dead end. Then consider the game starting with w0 played by I. The only way for II to win is to pass and since σ is a winning strategy σ(w0) = pass. But then we see that w0 must be □-assigned in a play compatible with σ which is contrary to our initial assumption.

Suppose \(w_{0}\Vdash \neg p\). Since σ is well-aligned, we can see that every world is either ¬□-assigned (or □-assigned) in every play compatible with σ; thus, w0 is □-assigned in all plays compatible with σ. Suppose for a contradiction that \(w_{0}\Vdash \neg \Box p\). Then for some w1 with w0Rw1 we have \(w_{1}\Vdash \neg p\) and so w1 is □-assigned. Given that w0 is □-assigned, either w0was played by II or II passed and w0 as the first move by I in some pay of the game. Suppose w0 was played by II and suppose then that I then plays w1 after w0 in some play compatible with σ. But then since w0 and w1 are consecutive □-assigned worlds in a partial play, we have a witness to the misalignment of σ. Suppose II passed. Then 〈w0,w1〉 is a partial play in which we have consecutive □-assigned worlds, which contradicts the well-alignment of σ. □

Theorem

(9)\(\Box \exists p\neg \Box p\dashv \vdash \forall q\Box (\Box q\to \Diamond q)\).

Proof

(⊩)

Then by necessitation get

and so

$$ \Box\exists p\neg\Box p\vdash\forall q\Box(\Box q\to\Diamond q). $$

(⊣)

Then by necessition, we get

and so we have

$$ \forall q\Box(\Box q\to\Diamond q)\vdash\Box\exists p\neg\Box p. $$

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Meadows, T. Did Descartes make a Diagonal Argument?. J Philos Logic 51, 219–247 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-021-09620-w

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-021-09620-w

Keywords

Navigation