Skip to main content
Log in

Exploring the Status of Population Genetics: The Role of Ecology

  • Thematic Issue Article: The Meaning of "Theory" in Biology
  • Published:
Biological Theory Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The status of population genetics has become hotly debated among biologists and philosophers of biology. Many seem to view population genetics as relatively unchanged since the Modern Synthesis and have argued that subjects such as development were left out of the Synthesis. Some have called for an extended evolutionary synthesis or for recognizing the insignificance of population genetics. Yet others such as Michael Lynch have defended population genetics, declaring “nothing in evolution makes sense except in the light of population genetics” (a twist on Dobzhansky’s famous slogan that “nothing in biology makes sense except in the light of evolution”). Missing from this discussion is the use of population genetics to shed light on ecology and vice versa, beginning in the 1940s and continuing until the present day. I highlight some of that history through an overview of traditions such as ecological genetics and population biology, followed by a slightly more in-depth look at a contemporary study of the endangered California Tiger Salamander. I argue that population genetics is a powerful and useful tool that continues to be used and modified, even if it isn’t required for all evolutionary explanations or doesn’t incorporate all the causal factors of evolution.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Note that Lewontin, in the essay from which this quote is taken and elsewhere, is quick to point out the limitations of population genetics. Also, although the “auto mechanics” comment is a bit cryptic, it can be reasonably interpreted as meaning “that which gets things going.” Judging by Lewontin’s practice, if not always his stated views, Lewontin is a supporter of population genetics, albeit not as staunch as some.

  2. Okasha (2008) is even more explicit: “The basic structure of population-genetic theory has changed little since the days of Fisher, Haldane and Wright.”

  3. Lloyd (1988) articulates a confirmatory relationship between population genetics and ecology. Nothing I say here is meant to overturn her claims; instead, I mean only to describe an additional sort of relationship.

  4. That is, I will be leaving out discussion of, and citations to, much good work. To cover it all is a book(s) length project.

  5. Here it might be objected that neither of these is considered to be “real” ecology by ecologists. Personally, I have little taste for intra-disciplinary disputes about what counts as “real x” (for example, philosophers are often quick to dismiss other work because it does not count as “real philosophy”) and I tend to see them as more turf-protecting than substantive. Here I will just note that my claim is not that all aspects of ecology have been incorporated into population genetics, but rather just that some aspects have been. Moreover, I suspect that many population geneticists might not recognize these areas as “real” population genetics either. It would not be surprising if blended fields were not fully embraced by those at the core of each of the fields involved in the blend.

  6. For more, see, e.g., Kingsland (1985), Collins (1986), and Odenbaugh (2006).

  7. Here it might be objected that population genetics tracks only genotypes, not phenotypes. Below, however, we shall see some cases where population genetics models have in fact been used to track changes in phenotype frequencies over time. Of course, one of the criticisms made by proponents of EvoDevo still holds, namely that population genetics ignores the processes through which phenotypes develop out of genotypes.

  8. For elaboration of this point, see “The Origins of the Neutralist-Selectionist Debates,” a transcript of a discussion involving John Beatty, James Crow, Michael Dietrich, and Richard Lewontin (http://authors.library.caltech.edu/5456/1/hrst.mit.edu/hrs/evolution/public/transcripts/origins_transcript.html).

  9. The distinction between “ecological genetics” as involving ecological fieldwork and “population biology” as involving mathematical modeling that I am drawing here is not a strong one, i.e., I am not confident that those terms are consistently used in that way by contemporary biologists. But it appears that originally the terms had those connotations.

  10. Levins (1966) shows how different population biology models “all converge in supporting the theorem that environmental uncertainty leads to increased niche breadth” (pp. 426–427). One of the models is a “simple genetic model with one locus and two alleles” and draws on insights from R.A. Fisher (p. 425).

  11. Other work in this vein, and from around the same time period, includes that of León (1974) and Slatkin and Maynard Smith (1979).

  12. I agree with Roughgarden that the textbook is very clear, as well as being better than most in laying out key concepts and assumptions!

  13. Shaffer is now at the University of California, Los Angeles.

  14. Fitzpatrick and Shaffer elaborate, “The cues used by amphibians to emerge from their underground retreats in a Mediterranean climate are poorly understood. It is probably determined in part by physiological clocks and in part by how individuals experience the weather and other seasonal stimuli in their subterranean terrestrial habitat, rather than by the pond in which they will breed. Nonrandom fertilization seems unlikely to be affected much by the pond environment, although spermatophores may spend several minutes in the open water prior to internal fertilization…. Other factors are more likely to have strong environment dependence. For example, visual or olfactory mate choice systems may be disrupted in the turbid, eutrophic water of artificial ponds, potentially explaining why there is a deficit of DLX3 heterozygotes only in the less turbid vernal pools. Alternatively, components of the physical or biotic environment may cause stronger viability selection on embryos and young larvae in vernal pools. The habitat-dependent heterozygote excess at HOXD8 could arise because cattle ponds may present immunological challenges that would be unusual in cleaner vernal pools, leading to balancing selection or heterosis in gene regions involved in pathogen response” (Fitzpatrick and Shaffer 2004, p. 1290). Although one referee of this paper suggested that Fitzpatrick and Shaffer’s explanation amounts to “hand waving,” I think it is an example of how knowledge of organisms in their habitats can help to overcome some of the problems with HWE analysis. Of course, such explanations are defeasible, as Fitzpatrick and Shaffer readily acknowledge.

  15. Note that my claim is not that the Shaffer Lab is the only, or even the first, to perform such studies. For example, the Collins Lab at ASU performed similar studies of a species of salamander native to Arizona, raising many similar ethical and policy issues (Jones et al. 1995; Maienschein et al. 1998; Storfer et al. 2004). Rather, my claim is that the Shaffer Lab studies are illustrative of many such excellent studies.

  16. Although Fitzpatrick and Shaffer certainly go beyond a one-locus, two-allele model!.

  17. Their BAPS software, looking for significant allele frequency differences, identified 15 different populations.

  18. As Wilson and Rannala explain, “The method requires fewer assumptions than estimators of long-term gene flow and can be legitimately applied to nonstationary populations that are far from genetic equilibrium. Moreover, the newly proposed method relaxes a key assumption of previous nonequilibrium methods for assigning individuals to populations and identifying migrants—namely that genotypes are in Hardy–Weinberg equilibrium within populations. We allow arbitrary genotype frequency distributions within populations by incorporating a separate inbreeding coefficient for each population. The joint probability distribution of inbreeding coefficients is estimated from the data” (2003, p. 1178).

References

  • Antonovics J (1992) Towards community genetics. In: Fritz RS, Simms EL (eds) Plant resistance to herbivores and pathogens: ecology, evolution, and genetics. University of Chicago Press, Chicago, pp 426–449

    Google Scholar 

  • Bailey JK, Genung MA, O’Reilly-Wapstra J, Potts B, Rowntree J, Schweitzer JA, Whitham TG (2012) New Phytol 193:24–26

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bromham L (2009) Does nothing in evolution make sense except in the light of population genetics? Biol Philos 24:387–403

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cain AJ, Sheppard PM (1950) Selection in the polymorphic land snail Cepaea nemoralis. Heredity 4:275–294

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cain AJ, Sheppard PM (1954) Natural selection in Cepaea. Genetics 39:89–116

    Google Scholar 

  • Carroll SB (2006) Endless forms most beautiful: the new science of evo devo and the making of the animal kingdom. Norton, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Collins JP (1986) “Evolutionary Ecology” and the use of natural selection in ecological theory. J Hist Biol 19:257–288

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Collins JP (2011) Natural selection and ecological theory. Presentation, 25th Altenberg workshop in theoretical biology: the meaning of “Theory” in biology. Konrad Lorenz Institute for Evolution and Cognition Research, Altenberg (July)

  • Darden L (1991) Theory change in science: strategies from Mendelian genetics. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Dupré J (1993) The disorder of things. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Epling C, Dobzhansky T (1942) Genetics of natural populations. Vi. Microgeographic races in Linanthus Parryae. Genetics 27:317–332

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisher RA, Ford EB (1947) The spread of a gene in natural conditions in a colony of the moth Panaxia Dominula L. Heredity 1:143–174

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fitzpatrick BM, Shaffer HB (2004) Environment-dependent admixture dynamics in a tiger salamander hybrid zone. Evolution 58:1282–1293

    Google Scholar 

  • Fitzpatrick BM, Shaffer HB (2007) Introduction history and habitat variation explain the landscape genetics of hybrid tiger salamanders. Ecol Appl 17:598–608

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ford EB (1964) Ecological genetics. Chapman and Hall, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Futuyma DJ (2010) Evolutionary biology: 150 years of progress. In: Bell MA, Futuyma DJ, Eanes WF, Levinton JS (eds) Evolution since Darwin: the first 150 Years. Sinauer, Sunderland, MA, pp 3–29

    Google Scholar 

  • Gerson EM (2007) The juncture of evolutionary and developmental biology. In: Laubichler M, Maienschein J (eds) From embryology to evo-devo: a history of developmental evolution. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, pp 435–464

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodnight CJ (1991) Intermixing ability in two-species communities of flour beetles. Am Natur 138:342–354

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griesemer J (2012) Models as mediators in the exact and inexact biological sciences. Biol Theory 7

  • Hastings A (1997) Population biology: concepts and models. Springer, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ho MW, Saunders PT (1979) Beyond neo-Darwinism: an epigenetic approach to evolution. J Theor Biol 78:573–591

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hull DL (1988) Science as a process: an evolutionary account of the social and conceptual development of science. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Jones TR, Routman EJ, Begun D, Collins JP (1995) Ancestry of an isolated subspecies of salamander, Ambystoma Tigrinum Stebbinsi (Lowe): the evolutionary significance of hybridization. Mol Phylogenet Evol 4:194–202

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kettlewell HBD (1955) Selection experiments on industrial melanism in the Lepidoptera. Heredity 9:323–342

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kettlewell HBD (1956) Further selection experiments on industrial melanism in the Lepidoptera. Heredity 10:287–301

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kingsland SE (1985) Modeling nature: episodes in the history of population ecology. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn TS (1970) The structure of scientific revolutions, 2nd edn. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakatos I (1978) The methodology of scientific research programmes. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lamotte M (1951) Recherches sur la structure génétique des populations naturelles de Cepaea Nemoralis (L.). Bulletin Biologique de la France et de la Belgique (Suppl.) 35:1–238

  • Lamotte M (1959) Polymorphism of natural populations of Cepaea Nemoralis. Cold Spring Harb Symp Quant Biol 24:65–84

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lande R (1988) Genetics and demography in biological conservation. Science 241:1455–1460

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Léon JA (1974) Selection in contexts of interspecific competition. Am Natur 108:739–757

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levins R (1966) The strategy of model building in population biology. Am Sci 54:421–431

    Google Scholar 

  • Levins R (1968) Evolution in changing environments. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewontin RC (1965) Selection for colonizing ability. In: Baker HG, Stebbins GL (eds) The genetics of colonizing species. Academic Press, New York, pp 77–91

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewontin RC (2000) The problems of population genetics. In: Singh RS, Krimbas CB (eds) Evolutionary genetics. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 5–23

    Google Scholar 

  • Lloyd EA (1988) The structure and confirmation of evolutionary theory. Greenwood Press, Westport, CT

    Google Scholar 

  • Longino HE (2012) The social life of scientific theories: a case study from behavioral sciences. Biol Theory 7. doi:10.1007/s13752-012-0053-3

  • Lynch M (2007) The frailty of adaptive hypotheses for the origins of organismal complexity. Proc Natl Acad Sci 104(Suppl. 1):8597–8604

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • MacArthur R (1962) Some generalized theorems of natural selection. Proc Natl Acad Sci 48:1893–1897

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • MacArthur R (1965) Ecological consequences of natural selection. In: Waterman TH, Morowitz HJ (eds) Theoretical and mathematical biology. Blaisdell, New York, pp 388–397

    Google Scholar 

  • MacArthur R, Levins R (1967) The limiting similarity, convergence and divergence of coexisting species. Am Natur 101:377–385

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • MacArthur R, Wilson EO (1967) The theory of island biogeography. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Maienschein J, Collins JP, Strouse D (1998) Biology and law: challenges of adjudicating competing claims in a democracy. Jurimetrics 38:151–181

    Google Scholar 

  • Manel S, Schwartz MK, Luikart G, Taberlet P (2003) Landscape genetics: combining landscape ecology and population genetics. Trends Ecol Evol 18:189–197

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Michod RE (1981) Positive heuristics in evolutionary biology. Brit J Philos Sci 32:1–36

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Millstein RL (2002) Are random drift and natural selection conceptually distinct? Biol Philos 17:33–53

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Millstein RL (2008) Distinguishing drift and selection empirically: “The Great Snail Debate” of the 1950s. J Hist Biol 41:339–367

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Millstein RL (2009) Concepts of drift and selection in “the Great Snail Debate” of the 1950s and early 1960s. In: Cain J, Ruse M (eds) Descended from Darwin: insights into the history of evolutionary studies, 1900–1970. American Philosophical Society, Philadelphia, pp 271–298

    Google Scholar 

  • Millstein RL, Skipper RA (2007) Population genetics. In: Hull DL, Ruse M (eds) The Cambridge companion to the philosophy of biology. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 22–43

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Millstein RL, Skipper RA, Dietrich MR (2009) (Mis)interpreting mathematical models: drift as a physical process. Philos Theory Biol 1:1–13

    Google Scholar 

  • Neuhauser C, Andow DA, Heimpel GE, May G, Shaw RG, Wagenius S (2003) Community genetics: expanding the synthesis of ecology and genetics. Ecology 84:545–558

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Odenbaugh J (2006) The strategy of “The strategy of model building in population biology.”. Biol Philos 21:607–621

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Odling-Smee JF, Laland KN, Feldman MW (2003) Niche construction: the neglected process in evolution. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Okasha S (2008) Population genetics. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Fall 2008 edn

  • Orr HA (1995) The population genetics of speciation: the evolution of hybrid incompatibilities. Genetics 139:1805–1813

    Google Scholar 

  • Pigliucci M (2008) The proper role of population genetics in modern evolutionary theory. Biol Theory 3:316–324

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pigliucci M (2009) An extended synthesis for evolutionary biology. Ann N Y Acad Sci 1168:218–228

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pigliucci M, Kaplan JM (2006) Making sense of evolution: the conceptual foundations of evolutionary biology. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Roughgarden J (1996) Theory of population genetics and evolutionary ecology: an introduction. Benjamin Cummings, Menlo Park, CA

    Google Scholar 

  • Singh RS, Uyenoyama MK (2009) The evolution of population biology. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Slatkin M, Maynard Smith J (1979) Models of coevolution. Q Rev Biol 54:233–263

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Slobodkin LB (1961) Growth and regulation of animal populations. Holt, Rinehart, and Winston, New York

  • Storfer AS, Mech SG, Reudink MW, Ziemba RE, Warren J, Collins JP (2004) Evidence for introgression in the endangered Sonora tiger salamander, Ambystoma tigrinum stebbinsi (Lowe). Copeia 4:783–796

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Storfer A, Murphy MA, Evans JS, Goldberg CS, Robinson S, Spear SF, Dezzani R, Delmelle E, Vierling L, Waits LP (2006) Putting the “landscape” in landscape genetics. Heredity 98:128–142

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Storfer A, Murphy MA, Spear SF, Holderegger R, Waits LP (2010) Landscape genetics: Where are we now? Mol Ecol 19:3496–3514

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Via S (2002) The ecological genetics of speciation. Am Natur 159:S1–S7

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wade MJ (2003) Community genetics and species interactions. Ecology 84:583–585

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wang IJ, Savage WK, Shaffer HB (2009) Landscape genetics and least-cost path analysis reveal unexpected dispersal routes in the California tiger salamander (Ambystoma Californiense). Mol Ecol 18:1365–1374

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Whitham TG, Young W, Martinsen GD, Gehring CA, Schweitzer JA, Wimp Shuster SM, Fischer DGGM, Bailey JK, Lindroth RL, Woolbright S, Kuske CR (2003) Community genetics: a consequence of the extended phenotype. Ecology 84:559–573

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Whitham TG, Bailey JK, Schweitzer JA, Shuster SM, Bangert RK, LeRoy CJ, Lonsdorf EV, Allan GJ, DiFazio SP, Potts BM, Fischer DG, Gehring CA, Lindroth RL, Marks JC, Hart SC, Wimp GM, Wooley SC (2006) A framework for community and ecosystem genetics: from genes to ecosystems. Nat Rev Genet 7:510–523

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson GA, Rannala R (2003) Bayesian inference of recent migration rates using multilocus genotypes. Genetics 163:1177–1191

    Google Scholar 

  • Wright S (1943) An analysis of local variability of flower color in Linanthus Parryae. Genetics 28:139–156

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

Thanks to Jim Collins, Lisa Gannett, Elihu Gerson, Jim Griesemer, Jon Hodge, Jay Odenbaugh, Alirio Rosales, and Rob Skipper for extremely helpful comments, and to Massimo Pigliucci and an anonymous referee for raising a number of concerns that I have attempted to address here. Thanks also to the Konrad Lorenz Institute for Evolution and Cognition Research, Werner Callebaut, Massimo Pigliucci, and Kim Sterelny for the invitation to the workshop.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Roberta L. Millstein.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Millstein, R.L. Exploring the Status of Population Genetics: The Role of Ecology. Biol Theory 7, 346–357 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13752-012-0056-0

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13752-012-0056-0

Keywords

Navigation