Skip to main content
Log in

Abduction − the context of discovery + underdetermination = inference to the best explanation

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The relationship between Peircean abduction and the modern notion of Inference to the Best Explanation (IBE) is a matter of dispute. Some philosophers, such as Harman (Philos Rev 74(1):88–95, 1965) and Lipton (Inference to the best explanation, Routledge, London, 1991, p. 58; 2004, p. 56), claim that abduction and IBE are virtually the same. Others, however, hold that they are quite different (Hintikka in Trans Charles S. Peirce Soc 34(3):503, 1998; Minnameier in Erkenntnis 60(1):75–105, 2004) and there is no link between them (Campos in Synthese 180(3):419–442, 2009). In this paper, I argue that neither of these views is correct. I show that abduction and IBE have important similarities as well as differences. Moreover, by bringing a historical perspective to the study of the relationship between abduction and IBE—a perspective that is lacking in the literature—I show that their differences can be well understood in terms of two historic developments in the history of philosophy of science: first, Reichenbach’s distinction between the context of discovery and the context of justification—and the consequent jettisoning of the context of discovery from philosophy of science—and second, underdetermination of theory by data.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. References to Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce (Peirce 1931–1935, 1958) are of the form (volume number. paragraph number, date).

  2. For an even longer list of philosophical works in which abduction and IBE are taken to be virtually identical, see (McAuliffe 2015).

  3. Some advocates of the Generative Interpretation of abduction are Davis (1972, Chapter II), Hintikka (1998), Burton (2000), and Minnameier (2004).

  4. I borrow the terms ‘the Generative Interpretation’ and ‘the Pursuitworthiness Interpretation’ from McKaughan (2008).

  5. Some advocates of the Pursuitworthiness Interpretation of abduction are Laudan (1980), Achinstein (1993), and McKaughan (2008).

  6. References to Peirce’s The New Elements of Mathematics (1976) are of the form (NEM volume number: page number, date).

  7. References to the eighth volumes of Writings of Charles S. Peirce: A Chronological Edition (2010) are of the form (W8: page number, date).

  8. See, for instance, Kuhn (1977), Quine and Ullian (1978, Chapter vi), Hempel (1979), and Laudan (1984).

  9. For instance, Newton-Smith (1981, pp. 226–32), McMullin (1996), Lipton (2004, Chapter 9), and Schindler (2018).

  10. This is not an accurate description of Semmelweis’s research. Through a close historical examination of his research, Tulodziecki (2013) convincingly argues that Semmelweis was not as perfect a reasoner as he is depicted by many philosophers of science—including Lipton—to be. For instance, at different stages of his research, he was simply ignoring available alternative explanations.

  11. Hintikka (1998) distinguishes between abduction and IBE on the ground that the latter is more akin to deduction. Minnameier (2004), however, claims that abduction is different from IBE, because the latter is similar to Peirce’s concept of induction. Campos (2009), too, extensively discusses the fact that abduction has nothing to do with confirming (or disconfirming) evidence for a hypothesis—i.e., has nothing to do with induction—while IBE is similar to induction.

  12. The book was later translated into English as The Theory of Probability (1949).

  13. Having a high view of Peirce’s theory of induction and probability and, at the same time, ignoring (if not disdaining) his theory of abduction could be seen among other philosophers too. Braithwaite (1934), for instance, claims that Peirce’s theory of probability and induction is one of the most important parts of his logic but there is nothing substantial in his theory of abduction in general, and insight in particular.

  14. Howard (2006, p. 4) convincingly argues that the DJ distinction also targets the left wing of the Vienna Circle, especially Neurath (1913).

  15. I am in debt of Don Howard who brought my attention to this work.

  16. The close association of the DJ distinction and the logical empiricist movement neither means that the DJ distinction did not survive the demise of logical empiricism nor that it was not accepted by philosophers unsympathetic to this movement. In fact, a precursor of the DJ distinction was introduced in the German edition of Popper’s The Logic of Scientific Discovery (2002, p. 7, originally published in 1934), four years before its appearance in Reichenbach’s works.

  17. In his works, Peirce mentions Poincaré’s name and views several times (5.495-7, 1906; 6.370, 1902).

  18. To the best of my knowledge, there is no evidence suggesting that Peirce was familiar with Pierre Duhem or his The Aim and Structure of Physical Theory (1954, French: 1906) which is considered by many as the locus classicus of underdetermination.

  19. References to The Essential Peirce: Selected Philosophical Writings (Peirce 1998) are of the form (EP volume number: page number, date).

  20. Peirce wrote a review on the English translation of Lobatchewsky’s Geometrical Researches on the Theory of Parallels (1891) in which he acknowledges that Lobatchewsky’s geometry “may, for all we can yet observe, be the system of nature” (W8: 217, 1892).

  21. For great discussions about Peirce’s revisions to his early pragmatic maxim, see Misak (2004, pp. 2–5) and Atkin (2016, Chapter 2). In my following discussion, I heavily draw on these works, especially on Atkin’s.

  22. I do not suggest that Peirce values “applies science” more than “pure science.” Quite conversely, he thinks that the latter is more valuable than the former. In fact, he encourages investment in applied sciences, because they make a great profit so we can spend more money on pure science (NEM4: 63, 1902). I just want to make it clear that Peirce cares about the economic aspects of scientific research.

References

  • Achinstein, P. (1993). How to defend a theory without testing it: Niles Bohr and the “logic of pursuit”. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 18(1), 90–120.

    Google Scholar 

  • Atkin, A. (2016). Peirce. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barnes, E. (1995). Inference to the loveliest explanation. Synthese, 103(2), 251–277.

    Google Scholar 

  • Braithwaite, R. B. (1934). Review of Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce (vol. I–IV). Mind, 43(172), 487–511.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burton, R. G. (2000). The problems of control in abduction. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society, 36(1), 149.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campos, D. G. (2009). On the distinction between Peirce’s abduction and Lipton’s Inference to the Best Explanation. Synthese, 180(3), 419–442.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davis, W. H. (1972). Peirce’s epistemology. The Hague: Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Regt, H. C. D. G. (1999). Peirce’s pragmatism, scientific realism, and the problem of underdetermination. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society, 35(2), 374–397.

    Google Scholar 

  • Delaney, C. F. (1982). Peirce on “Simplicity” and the conditions of the possibility of science. In J. D. Collins & L. J. Thro (Eds.), History of philosophy in the making: A symposium of essays to honor Professor James D. Collins on his 65th birthday (pp. 177–194). Washington, DC: University Press of America.

    Google Scholar 

  • Delaney, C. F. (1993). Science, knowledge, and mind: A study in the philosophy of C.S. Peirce. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duhem, P. (1954). The aim and structure of physical theory. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fann, K. T. (1970). Peirce’s theory of abduction. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • French, S. (1989). A Peircean response to the realist-empiricist debate. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society, 25(3), 293–307.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (1983). Representing and intervening: Introductory topics in the philosophy of natural science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hanson, N. R. (1958). Patterns of discovery: An inquiry into the conceptual foundations of science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. (1965). The inference to the best explanation. The Philosophical Review, 74(1), 88–95.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. G. (1965a). Science and human values. In Aspects of scientific explanation and other essays in the philosophy of science (pp. 81–96). New York: The Free Press.

  • Hempel, C. G. (1965b). Studies in the logic of confirmation. In Aspects of scientific explanation and other essays in the philosophy of science (pp. 3–46). New York: The Free Press.

  • Hempel, C. G. (1966). Philosophy of natural science. Upper Saddle River, NJ: Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. G. (1966/2001). Recent problems of induction. In J. H. Fetzer (Ed.), The philosophy of Carl G. Hempel: Studies in science, explanation, and rationality (pp. 29–48). New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Hempel, C. G. (1979). Scientific rationality: Analytic vs. pragmatic perspectives. In T. S. Geraets (Ed.), Rationality to-day/la rationalite ajiourd’hui (pp. 46–58). Ottawa: The University of Ottawa Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. G. (1990/2000). The irrelevance of the concept of truth for the critical appraisal of scientific theories. In R. Jeffrey (Ed.), Selected philosophical essays (pp. 75–84). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Hintikka, J. (1998). What is abduction? The fundamental problem of contemporary epistemology. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society, 34(3), 503.

    Google Scholar 

  • Howard, D. (2003). Two left turns make a right: on the curious political career of North American philosophy of science at midcentury. In G. L. Hardcastle & A. W. Richardson (Eds.), Logical Empiricism in North America (pp. 25–93). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Howard, D. (2006). Lost wanderers in the forest of knowledge: Some thoughts on the discovery-justification distinction. In J. Schickore & F. Steinle (Eds.), Revisiting discovery and justification: Historical and philosophical perspectives on the context distinction (pp. 3–22). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. S. (1977). Objectivity, value judgment, and theory choice. In The essential tension: Selected studies in scientific tradition and change (pp. 320–339). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

  • Laudan, L. (1980). Why was the logic of discovery abandoned? In T. Nickles (Ed.), Scientific discovery, logic, and rationality (pp. 173–183). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, L. (1984). Science and values: The aims of science and their role in scientific debate. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levi, I. (1995). Induction according to Peirce. In K. L. Ketner (Ed.), Peirce and contemporary thought: Philosophical inquiries (pp. 59–93). New York: Fordham University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lipton, P. (1991). Inference to the best explanation. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lipton, P. (2004). Inference to the best explanation (2nd ed.). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Magnus, P. D. (2005). Peirce: Underdetermination, agnosticism, and related mistakes. Inquiry, 48(1), 26–37.

    Google Scholar 

  • McAuliffe, W. H. B. (2015). How did abduction get confused with inference to the best explanation? Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society, 51(3), 300–319.

    Google Scholar 

  • McKaughan, D. J. (2008). From ugly duckling to swan: C. S. Peirce, abduction, and the pursuit of scientific theories. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society, 44(3), 446–468.

    Google Scholar 

  • McMullin, E. (1996). Epistemic virtue and theory appraisal. In I. Douven & L. Horsten (Eds.), Realism in the sciences (pp. 13–34). Leuven: Leuven University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Minnameier, G. (2004). Peirce-suit of truth—Why inference to the best explanation and abduction ought not to be confused. Erkenntnis, 60(1), 75–105.

    Google Scholar 

  • Misak, C. (Ed.). (2004). Charles Sanders Peirce (1839–1914). In The Cambridge companion to Peirce (pp. 1–26). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Mohammadian, M. (2019). Beyond the instinct-inference dichotomy: A unified interpretation of Peirce’s theory of abduction. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society, 55(2).

  • Musgrave, A. (1988). The ultimate argument for scientific realism. In R. Nola (Ed.), Relativism and realism in science (pp. 229–252). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E. (1936). Review of Wahrscheinlichkeitslehre. Mind, 45(180), 501–514.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neurath, O. (1913). The lost wanderers of Descartes and the auxiliary motive (on the psychology of decision). In R. S. Cohen & M. Neurath (Eds.), Philosophical papers 1913–1946 (pp. 1–12). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Newton-Smith, W. H. (1981). The rationality of science. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Paavola, S. (2006). Hansonian and Harmanian abduction as models of discovery. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 20(1), 93–108.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, C. S. (1931–1935). Collected papers of Charles Sanders Peirce. (C. Harteshorne & P. Weiss, Eds.) (Vols. 1–8, Vol. 1–6). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

  • Peirce, C. S. (1958). Collected papers of Charles Sanders Peirce. (A. W. Burks, Ed.) (Vols. 1–8, Vol. 7–8). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

  • Peirce, C. S. (1976). The new elements of mathematics. (C. Eisele, Ed.) (Vols. 1–4, Vol. 4). The Hague: Mouton (Abbreviated NEM).

  • Peirce, C. S. (1998). The essential Peirce: Selected philosophical writings (Vols. 1–2, Vol. 2). Bloomington: Indiana University Press (Abbreviated EP2.).

    Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, C. S. (2010). Writings of Charles S. Peirce: A chronological edition, volume 8: 1890–1892. Bloomington: Indiana University Press (Abbreviated W8.).

    Google Scholar 

  • Poincaré, H. (1905). Science and hypothesis. London: Walter Scott Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. (2002). The logic of scientific discovery. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V., & Ullian, J. S. (1978). The web of belief (2nd ed.). New York: McGraw-Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reichenbach, H. (1938a). Experience and prediction: An analysis of the foundations and the structure of knowledge. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reichenbach, H. (1938b). On probability and induction. Philosophy of Science, 5(1), 21–45.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reichenbach, H. (1939). Dewey’s theory of science. In P. A. Schilpp (Ed.), The philosophy of John Dewey (pp. 159–192). Chicago: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reichenbach, H. (1949). The theory of probability: An inquiry into the logical and mathematical foundations of the calculus of probability. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reichenbach, H. (1951). The rise of scientific philosophy. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Richardson, A. W. (2006). Freedom in a scientific society: Reading the context of Reichenbach’s contexts. In J. Schickore & F. Steinle (Eds.), Revisiting discovery and justification: Historical and philosophical perspectives on the context distinction (pp. 41–54). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schickore, J. (2018). Scientific discovery. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2018/entries/scientific-discovery/ Accessed November 17, 2018.

  • Schilpp, P. A. (Ed.). (1939). The philosophy of John Dewey. Chicago: Northwestern University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schindler, S. (2018). Theoretical virtues in science: Uncovering reality through theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stewart, W. C. (1991). Social and economic aspects of Peirce’s conception of science. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society, 27(4), 501–526.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tulodziecki, D. (2013). Shattering the myth of Semmelweis. Philosophy of Science, 80(5), 1065–1075.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Thanks to Anjan Chakravartty, Sara Bernstein, Daniel Nolan, Ryan O’Loughlin, and two anonymous reviewers for their thoughtful comments. I also thank Ashton Green for her helpful suggestions.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Mousa Mohammadian.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Mohammadian, M. Abduction − the context of discovery + underdetermination = inference to the best explanation. Synthese 198, 4205–4228 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02337-z

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02337-z

Keywords

Navigation