Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-ttngx Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-08T16:17:40.729Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Bayesian Decision Theory and Stochastic Independence

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2022

Abstract

As stochastic independence is essential to the mathematical development of probability theory, it seems that any foundational work on probability should be able to account for this property. Bayesian decision theory appears to be wanting in this respect. Savage’s postulates on preferences under uncertainty entail a subjective expected utility representation, and this asserts only the existence and uniqueness of a subjective probability measure, regardless of its properties. What is missing is a preference condition corresponding to stochastic independence. To fill this significant gap, the article axiomatizes Bayesian decision theory afresh and proves several representation theorems in this novel framework.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © The Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

A first version of this article was presented at a seminar at the Munich Center for Mathematical Philosophy and at the Theoretical Aspects of Rationality and Knowledge (TARK) 2017 conference. The current version has particularly benefited from detailed comments made by Richard Bradley, Donald Gillies, Robert Nau, Marcus Pivato, Burkhard Schipper, Peter Wakker, Paul Weirich, two anonymous TARK referees, and two anonymous referees of this journal. I thank the Investissements d’Avenir (ANR-11-IDEX-0003/Labex Ecodec/ANR-11-LABX-0047) for supporting this research.

References

Anscombe, F. J., and Aumann, R. J. 1963. “A Definition of Subjective Probability.” Annals of Mathematical Statistics 34:199205.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Battigalli, P., and Veronesi, P. 1996. “A Note on Stochastic Independence without Savage-Null Events.” Journal of Economic Theory 70:235–48.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bernardo, J. M., Fernandez, J. R., and Smith, A. F. M. 1985. “The Foundations of Decision Theory: An Intuitive, Operational Approach with Mathematical Extensions.” Theory and Decision 19:127–50.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blackorby, C., Primont, D., and Russell, R. R. 1978. Duality, Separability and Functional Structures: Theory and Applications. New York: North-Holland.Google Scholar
Blume, L., Brandenburger, A., and Dekel, E. 1991. “Lexicographic Probability and Choice under Uncertainty.” Econometrica 59:6179.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bradley, R. 2017. Decision Theory with a Human Face. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Debreu, G. 1954. “Representation of a Preference Ordering by a Numerical Function.” In Decision Processes, ed. Thrall, R. M., Combs, C. H., and Davis, R. L., 159–65. New York: Wiley. Repr. as chap. 6 in G. Debreu, Mathematical Economics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1983).Google Scholar
Debreu, G. 1960. “Topological Methods in Cardinal Utility Theory.” In Mathematical Methods in the Social Sciences, 1959, ed. Arrow, K. J., Karlin, S., and Suppes, P., 1626. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press. Repr. as chap. 9 in G. Debreu, Mathematical Economics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1983).Google Scholar
de Finetti, B. 1931. Probabilismo. Biblioteca di filosofica. Napoli: Perrella. Repr. in B. de Finetti, La logica dell’incerto (Milan: Il Saggiatore, 1989), 370. English trans. “Probabilism,” Erkenntnis 31 (1989): 169-223..Google Scholar
Domotor, Z. 1969. “Probabilistic Relational Structures and Their Applications.” Technical Report 144, Institute for Mathematical Studies in the Social Sciences, Stanford University.Google Scholar
Ergin, H., and Gul, F. 2009. “A Theory of Subjective Compound Lotteries.” Journal of Economic Theory 144:899929.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feller, W. 1968. An Introduction to Probability Theory and Its Applications. 3rd ed. New York: Wiley.Google Scholar
Fine, T. L. 1973. Theories of Probability: An Examination of Foundations. New York: Academic Press.Google Scholar
Fishburn, P. C. 1970. Utility Theory for Decision Making. New York: Wiley.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fitelson, B., and Hájek, A. 2017. “Declarations of Independence.” Synthese 194:3979–95.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fleurbaey, M., and Mongin, P. 2016. “The Utilitarian Relevance of the Aggregation Theorem.” American Economic Journal: Microeconomics 8:289306.Google Scholar
Gilboa, I. 2009. Theory of Decision under Uncertainty. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gillies, D. 2000. Philosophical Theories of Probability. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Gorman, W. 1968. “The Structure of Utility Functions.” Review of Economic Studies 35:367–90.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Halmos, P. R. 1974. Measure Theory. New York: Springer.Google Scholar
Hoel, P. G., Port, S.C., and Stone, C. J. 1971. Introduction to Probability Theory. Boston: Houghton-Mifflin.Google Scholar
Jeffrey, R. 1983. The Logic of Decision. 2nd ed. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Joyce, J. M. 1998. “A Non-pragmatic Vindication of Probabilism.” Philosophy of Science 65:575603.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Joyce, J. M. 1999. The Foundations of Causal Decision Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kaplan, M., and Fine, T. L. 1977. “Joint Orders in Comparative Probability.” Annals of Probability 5:161–79.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Keeney, R. L., and Raiffa, H. 1993. Decisions with Multiple Objectives: Preferences and Value Tradeoffs. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Klibanoff, P., Marinacci, M., and Mukerji, S. 2005. “A Smooth Model of Decision Making under Ambiguity.” Econometrica 73 (6): 1849–92.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kolmogorov, A. N. 1933. Grundbegriffe der Wahrscheinlichkeitsrechnung. Ergebnisse der Mathematik und ihrer Grenzgebiete 3. Berlin: Springer. Trans. Nathan Morrison as Foundations of the Theory of Probability, 2nd ed. (New York: Chelsea, 1956).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leitgeb, H., and Pettigrew, R. 2010. “An Objective Justification of Bayesianism II: The Consequences of Minimizing Inaccuracy.” Philosophy of Science 77:236–72.Google Scholar
Luce, R. D., and Narens, L. 1978. “Qualitative Independence in Probability Theory.” Theory and Decision 9:225–39.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mongin, P., and Pivato, M. 2015. “Ranking Multidimensional Alternatives and Uncertain Prospects.” Journal of Economic Theory 157:146–71.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nau, R. F. 2006. “Uncertainty Aversion with Second-Order Utilities and Probabilities.” Management Science 52:136–45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pfanzagl, J. 1968. Theory of Measurement. New York: Wiley.Google Scholar
Popper, K. R. 1972. The Logic of Scientific Discovery. 6th ed. London: Hutchinson.Google Scholar
Rado, F., and Baker, J. 1987. “Pexider’s Equation and Aggregation of Allocations.” Aequationes Mathematicae 32:227–39.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rényi, A. 1955. “On a New Axiomatic Theory of Probability.” Acta Mathematica Academiae Scientiae Hungaricae 6:268335.Google Scholar
Savage, L. J. 1972. The Foundations of Statistics. 2nd ed. (1st ed. 1954) New York: Wiley.Google Scholar
Wakker, P. 1989. Additive Representations of Preferences. Dordrecht: Kluwer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wakker, P. 2010. Prospect Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar