Skip to main content
Log in

Mental Structures as Biosemiotic Constraints on the Functions of Non-human (Neuro)Cognitive Systems

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Biosemiotics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper approaches the question of how to describe the higher-level internal structures and representations of cognitive systems across various kinds of nonhuman (neuro)cognitive systems. While much research in cognitive (neuro)science and comparative cognition is dedicated to the exploration of the (neuro)cognitive mechanisms and processes with a focus on brain-behavior relations across different non-human species, not much has been done to connect (neuro)cognitive mechanisms and processes and the associated behaviors to plausible higher-level structures and representations of distinct kinds of cognitive systems in non-humans. Although the study of (neuro)cognitive mechanisms and processes can certainly be revealing, (neuro)cognitive mechanisms and processes are underspecified with respect to internal structures and representations of non-human cognitive systems because multiple such mechanisms can target, or be mapped onto, the same internal structure or vice versa. This paper outlines a biosemiotic approach to this linking problem in order to bridge the gap between functions of (neuro)cognitive systems in different species and the higher-level cognitive structures and representations. It is contended that the higher-level internal structures and representations of various cognitive systems are biosemiotic constraints on the (biological) functions of (neuro)cognitive systems that serve to restrict the range of functions (neuro)cognitive systems have or are selected for. This turns out to have implications for issues on the convergent evolution of cognitive traits.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4
Fig. 5
Fig. 6
Fig. 7

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. These include conception, conceptualization, association, categorization processes that are delinked from immediate sensory stimuli.

  2. Even a strictly situated approach to cognition for non-human species does not rule out the possibility of representations or internal structures because certain cognitive tasks such as transitive inference, comparison, spatial search in non-humans etc. cannot bypass a reference to representations (see Cheng 2018). Neurocognitive functions are almost always at the interface between internal representations and forms and patterns of the external world as neural processes relate to actions in the external world.

  3. Since indices include icons as well, as pointed out by Emmeche (2004), it would not be surprising if some signals in animals and organisms turn out to be iconic with respect to the actions/responses (as in mimicry relations, for example).

  4. An analogy with research in language typology can help understand the concept better. Some regularities of linguistic categories are recurrent across languages all over the world. These recurrent regularities exist independently of parameters of geographical closeness, family-relatedness and the like. Strong recurrent patterns become universals (see Haspelmath 2019).

  5. Admittedly, the firm distinction between sign processes and mental structures may turn out to be relative due to the time-varying correlations of mental structures to behaviors, as pointed out by one anonymous referee. This may pose some difficulty in figuring out whether a given behavior in some species or in some individual member of the species always reliably permits the ascription of a certain mental structure. That is so because a given mental structure once identified or recognized cannot be recognized in the same way because the relevant behavior(s) that correlated with it once no longer remain(s) the same, or maybe the mental structure itself has changed. In such cases other plausible explanations for the changes may be warranted. One explanation is that either the mental structure has not changed but the relevant behavior has, or the behavior concerned has not changed but the mental structure has drastically changed. If the former holds true (that is, when the mental structure does not undergo any alteration but the behavior does), the sign relation(s) that the mental structure activates may not remain preserved as the responses/actions as part of the sign relation will change. But in the latter case the relevant relation specified in a mental structure will itself change and the sign relation(s) it activates may not change as the same responses/actions are produced. The former applies to cases such as the habituation of automatization of a cognitive process as a creature ceases to produce the same (re)action after encountering it repeatedly in its habitat. Even though the internal state remains the same, the responses/actions change. The latter may apply to situations in which a creature does produce the same responses/actions but the internal state must have changed due to changes in environments, motivation, time, emotions, and/or consciousness. Due to higher levels of motivation or heightened levels of consciousness in a short learning period a creature may produce the same response towards a class of objects but the internal state may change due to learning. For instance, domestic chicks have been observed to choose to go near an occluded triangle (as opposed to a triangle-like object with a piece missing) after being imprinted on a triangular shape. The explanation provided for this is that chicks, just like humans, do a sort of ‘filling in” for the occluded part of the triangle (see Marino 2017). Hence the internal state must change (after the filling-in), but the responses would not change (much). In any case, when both a mental structure and its linked sign relation change together, identifying or recognizing the mental structure may become harder and their boundaries may become fuzzier. Such cases may demand extensive observations over a long period for the detection of the sign relations recurrently in a cluster of similar and different circumstances so that the actual mental structure can be identified. Since the consideration of various factors in this regard is beyond the scope of this paper, we leave this matter open.

References

  • Anderson, M. L. (2014). After phrenology: Neural reuse and the interactive brain. Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arthur, W. (2011). Evolution: A developmental approach. Oxford: Wiley Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barbieri, M. (2014). From biosemiotics to code biology. Biological Theory, 9(2), 239–249.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barbieri, M. (2015). Code biology. A new science of life. Berlin: Springer.

  • Baron-Cohen, S. (1992). How monkeys do things with “words”. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 15, 148–149.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bennett, A. T. (1996). Do animals have cognitive maps? Journal of Experimental Biology, 199, 219–224.

  • Bermúdez, J. L. (2003). Thinking without words. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beran, M. J., Parrish, A. E., Perdue, B. M., & Washburn, D. A. (2014). Comparative cognition: Past, present, and future. International Journal of Comparative Psychology, 27, 3–30.

    PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Bertossa, R. C. (2011). Morphology and behaviour: Functional links in development and evolution. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London (B), 366, 2056–2068.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boogert, N. J., Madden, J. R., Morand-Ferron, J., & Thornton, A. (2018). Measuring and understanding individual differences in cognition. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London (B), 373(1756), 20170280. https://doi.org/10.1098/rstb.2017.0280.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bolhuis, J. J., & Wynne, C. D. (2009). Can evolution explain how minds work? Nature, 458(7240), 832–833. https://doi.org/10.1038/458832a.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Brier, S. (2000). Biosemiotics as a possible bridge between embodiment in cognitive semantics and the motivation concept of animal cognition in ethology. Cybernetics and Human Knowing, 7(1), 57–75.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cheng, K. (2018). Cognition beyond representation: Varieties of situated cognition in animals. Comparative Cognition & Behavior Reviews, 13, 1–20.

    CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Coolen, I., Dangles, O., & Casas, J. (2005). Social learning in noncolonial insects. Current Biology, 15, 1931–1935.

    CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Darwin, C. (1871). The descent of man, and selection in relation to sex. London: John Murray.

    Google Scholar 

  • Daw, N. D., Gershman, S. J., Seymour, B., Dayan, P., & Dolan, R. J. (2011). Model-based influences on humans’ choices and striatal prediction errors. Neuron, 69, 1204–1215.

    CAS  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Deacon, T. (1997). The symbolic species: The co-evolution of language and the human brain. New York: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deacon, T. (2012). Incomplete nature: How mind emerged from matter. New York: Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Waal, F. (2009). Darwin's last laugh. Nature, 460(7252), 175. https://doi.org/10.1038/460175a.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • de Waal, F. (2016). Are we smart enough to know how smart animals are? New York: Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dolan, R. J., & Dayan, P. (2013). Goals and habits in the brain. Neuron, 80(2), 312–325.

    CAS  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Doll, B. B., Jacobs, W. J., Sanfey, A. G., & Frank, M. J. (2009). Instructional control of reinforcement learning: A behavioral and neurocomputational investigation. Brain Research, 1299, 74–94.

    CAS  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Eaton, T., et al. (2018). Bottoms-up! Rejecting top-down human-centered approaches in comparative psychology. International Journal of Comparative Psychology, 31, 1–19.

    Google Scholar 

  • Emmeche, C. (2001). Does a robot have an Umwelt? Reflections on the qualitative biosemiotics of Jakob von Uexküll. Semiotica, 134(1/4), 653–693.

    Google Scholar 

  • Emmeche, C. (2004). Causal processes, semiosis, and consciousness. In J. Seibt (Ed.), Process theories: Crossdisciplinary studies in dynamic categories (pp. 313–336). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Emmeche, C., Stjernfelt, F., & Køppe, S. (2000). Levels, emergence, and three versions of downward causation. In P. B. Andersen, C. Emmeche, N. O. Finnemann, & P. V. Christiansen (Eds.), Downward causation: Minds, bodies and matter (pp. 13–34). Aarhus: Aarhus University Press.

  • Farina, A. (2012). A biosemiotic perspective of the resource criterion: Toward a general theory of resources. Biosemiotics, 5(1), 17–32.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feinberg, T. E., & Mallatt, J. M. (2016). The ancient origins of consciousness: How the brain created experience. Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feinberg, T. E., & Mallatt, J. M. (2018). Consciousness demystified. Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fitch, W. T. (2014). Toward a computational framework for cognitive biology: Unifying approaches from cognitive neuroscience and comparative cognition. Physics of Life Reviews, 11(3), 329–364.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Frasnelli, et al. (2014). The bee as a model to investigate brain and behavioural asymmetries. Insects., 5, 120–138.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gauker, C. (2011). Words and images: An essay on the origin of ideas. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibson, J. J. (1979). The ecological approach to visual perception. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gershman, S. J., Markman, A. B., & Otto, A. R. (2012). Retrospective revaluation in sequential decision making: A tale of two systems. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 143, 182–194.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giurfa, M., & Menzel, R. (2013). Cognitive components of insect behavior. In R. Menzel & P. R. Benjamin (Eds.), Invertebrate learning and memory (pp. 14–25). San Diego: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould, S. J. (2002). The structure of evolutionary theory. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hall, B. K. (2012a). Homology, homoplasy, novelty, and behavior. Developmental Psychobiology, 55(1), 4–12.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Hall, B. K. (2012b). Parallelism, deep homology, and evo-devo. Evolution & Development, 14(1), 29–33.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harms, W. F. (2004). Primitive content, translation and the emergence of meaning in animal communication. In D. K. Oller & U. Griebel (Eds.), Evolution of communication systems: A comparative approach (pp. 31–48). Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haspelmath, M. (2019). Can cross-linguistic regularities be explained by constraints on change? In K. Schmidtke-Bode et al. (Eds.), Explanation in typology: Diachronic sources, functional motivations and the nature of the evidence (pp. 1–24). Berlin: Language Science Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hobaiter, C., & Byrne, R. W. (2014). The meanings of chimpanzee gestures. Current Biology, 24(14), 1596–1600.

    CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Hoffmeyer, J. (2007). Semiotic scaffolding of living systems. In M. Barbieri (Ed.), Introduction to biosemiotics (pp. 149–166). Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hurford, J. R. (2007). The origins of meaning: Language in the light of evolution. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jablonka, E., & Ginsburg, S. (2019). The evolution of the sensitive soul. Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Japyassú, H. F., & Laland, K. N. (2017). Extended spider cognition. Animal Cognition, 20(3), 375–395.

    PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Jaroš, F., & Maran, T. (2019). Humans on top, humans among the other animals: Narratives of anthropological difference. Biosemiotics, 12, 1–23. https://doi.org/10.1007/s12304-019-09364-w.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kesner, R. (2013). Neurobiological foundations of an attribute model of memory. Comparative Cognition & Behavior Reviews, 8, 29–59.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kull, K. (2000). An introduction to phytosemiotics: Semiotic botany and vegetative sign systems. Sign Systems Studies, 28, 326–350.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lashley, K. S. (1951). The problem of serial order in behavior. In L. A. Jeffress (Ed.), Cerebral mechanisms in behavior: The Hixon symposium (pp. 112–146). New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Liebal, K., Waller, B. M., Slocombe, K. E., & Burrows, A. M. (2014). Primate communication: a multimodal approach. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Logan, C. J., Jelbert, S. A., Breen, A. J., Gray, R. D., & Taylor, A. H. (2014). Modifications to the Aesop’s fable paradigm change new Caledonian crow performances. PLoS One, 9(7), e103049. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0103049.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Logan, C. J., Harvey, B. D., Schlinger, B. A., & Rensel, M. (2016). Western scrub-jays do not appear to attend to functionality in Aesop’s fable experiments. PeerJ, 4, e1707. https://doi.org/10.7717/peerj.1707.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Logan, C., et al. (2018). Beyond brain size: Uncovering the neural correlates of behavioral and cognitive specialization. Comparative Cognition & Behavior Reviews, 13, 55–90.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lycan, W. (1999). Intentionality. In R. A. Wilson & F. Keil (Eds.), The MIT encyclopedia of the cognitive sciences (pp. 413–415). Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maran, T., & Kleisner, K. (2010). Towards an evolutionary biosemiotics: Semiotic selection and semiotic co-option. Biosemiotics, 3(2), 189–200.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marino, L. (2017). Thinking chickens: A review of cognition, emotion, and behavior in the domestic chicken. Animal Cognition, 20(2), 127–147.

    PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Maturana, H. R., & Varela, F. J. (1980). Autopoiesis and cognition: The realization of the living. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayr, E. (1982). The growth of biological thought: Diversity, evolution, and inheritance. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McGhee, G. R. (2011). Convergent evolution: Limited forms most beautiful. Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Melchner, L., Pallas, S. L., & Sur, M. (2000). Visual behaviour mediated by retinal projections directed to the auditory pathway. Nature, 404, 81–876.

    Google Scholar 

  • Menzel, R., Geiger, K., Müller, U., Joerges, J., & Chittka, L. (1998). Bees travel novel homeward routes by integrating spatially acquired vector memories. Animal Behaviour, 55, 139–152.

    CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Menzel, R., & Giurfa, M. (2001). Cognitive architecture of a mini-brain: The honeybee. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 5, 62–71.

    CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Menzel, R., Greggers, U., Smith, A., Berger, S., Brandt, R., Brunke, S., Bundrock, G., Hulse, S., Plumpe, T., Schaupp, F., Schuttler, E., Stach, S., Stindt, J., Stollhoff, N., & Watzl, S. (2005). Honeybees navigate according to a map-like spatial memory. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 102, 3040–3045.

    CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Mondal, P. (2017). Natural language and possible minds: How language uncovers the cognitive landscape of nature. Leiden: Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, C. L. (1894). An introduction to comparative psychology. London: W. Scott Ltd..

    Google Scholar 

  • Noë, R., & Laporte, M. (2014). Socio-spatial cognition in vervet monkeys. Animal Cognition, 17(3), 597–607.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Northoff, G. (2018). The spontaneous brain: From the mind–body to the world–brain problem. Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Piaget, J. (1951). Play, dreams and imitation in childhood. London: William Heinemann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Piaget, J. (1952). The origins of intelligence in children. New York: International University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Piaget, J. (1971). Biology and knowledge. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, C. S. (1906). The basis of pragmaticism. In C. Hartshorne & P. Weiss (Eds.), The collected papers of Charles Sanders Peirce (pp. 1931–1935). Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Penn, D. C., Holyoak, K. J., & Povinelli, D. J. (2008). Darwin’s mistake: Explaining the discontinuity between human and non-human minds. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 31, 109–178.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Petkov, C. I., & Wilson, B. (2012). On the pursuit of the brain network for proto-syntactic learning in nonhuman primates: Conceptual issues and neurobiological hypotheses. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London (B), 367, 2077–2088.

    Google Scholar 

  • Powell, R. (2012). Convergent evolution and the limits of natural selection. European Journal of Philosophy of Science, 2(3), 355–373.

    Google Scholar 

  • Queiroz, J. (2012). Dicent symbols in non-human semiotic processes. Biosemiotics, 5, 319–329.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reaume, C. J., & Sokolowski, M. B. (2011). Conservation of gene function in behaviour. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London (B), 366(1574), 2100–2110.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roth, G. (2013). The long evolution of brains and minds. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rowe, C., & Healy, S. D. (2014). Measuring variation in cognition. Behavioral Ecology, 25, 1287–1292.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rutishauser, R., & Moline, P. (2005). Evo-devo and the search for homology (“sameness”) in biological systems. Theory in Biosciences, 124, 213–241.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. (1983). Intentionality: An essay in the philosophy of mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sebeok, T. A. (1972). Perspectives in zoosemiotics. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sebeok, T. A. (2001). Signs: An introduction to semiotics. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Serpico, D., & Frasnelli, E. (2018). Where the standard approach in comparative neuroscience fails and where it works: General intelligence and brain asymmetries. Comparative Cognition & Behavioral Reviews, 13, 95–98.

    Google Scholar 

  • Seyfarth, R. M, Cheney, D. L., & Marler, P. (1980). Monkey responses to three different alarm calls: evidence of predator classification and semantic communication. Science, 210(4471), 801–803.

  • Shanahan, M. (2012). The brain's connective core and its role in animal cognition. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London (B), 367, 2704–2714.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sharov, A., Maran, T., & Tønnessen, M. (2015). Organisms reshape sign relations. Biosemiotics, 8, 361–365.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shaw, R. C., & Schmelz, M. (2017). Cognitive test batteries in animal cognition research: Evaluating the past, present and future of comparative psychometrics. Animal Cognition, 20(6), 1003–1018.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Sherry, D. F. (2006). Neuroecology. Annual Review of Psychology, 57, 167–197.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Shettleworth, S. J. (2012). Modularity, comparative cognition and human uniqueness. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London (B), 367, 2794–2802.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strausfeld, N. J., & Hirth, F. (2013). Deep homology of arthropod central complex and vertebrate basal ganglia. Science, 340(6129), 157–161.

    CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Suddendorf, T. (2013). The gap: The science of what separates us from other animals. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, E. (2010). Mind in life: Biology, phenomenology, and the sciences of mind. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tønnessen, M. (2010). Steps to a semiotics of being. Biosemiotics, 3, 375–392.

    Google Scholar 

  • Townsend, S. W., Koski, S. E., Byrne, R. W., Slocombe, K. E., Bickel, B., Boeckle, M., et al. (2017). Exorcising G rice's ghost: An empirical approach to studying intentional communication in animals. Biological Reviews, 92(3), 1427–1433.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Uexküll, J. (1921). Umwelt und innenwelt der tiere. Berlin: Julius Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Uexküll, J. (1982). The theory of meaning. Semiotica, 42, 25–82. (originally published in 1940).

  • Varella, M. A. C. (2018). The biology and evolution of the three psychological tendencies to anthropomorphize biology and evolution. Frontiers in Psychology, 9, 1839. https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2018.01839.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Vitti-Rodrigues, M., & Emmeche, C. (2017). Abduction: Can non-human animals make discoveries? Biosemiotics, 10, 295–313.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wechsler, B. (2019). Three levels of consciousness: A pattern in phylogeny and human ontogeny. International Journal of Comparative Psychology, 32, 1–29.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilcox, S., & Jackson, R. (2002). Jumping spider tricksters: Deceit, predation, and cognition. In M. Bekoff, C. Allen, & G. M. Burghardt (Eds.), The cognitive animal: Empirical and theoretical perspective on animal cognition (pp. 27–ss). Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Winters, A. M. (2014). The evolutionary relevance of abstraction and representation. Biosemiotics., 7, 125–139.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wong, T. Y. W. (2019). The evolutionary contingency thesis and evolutionary idiosyncrasies. Biology and Philosophy, 34, 22. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-019-9684-0.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Prakash Mondal.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of Interest

The author declares no conflict of interests.

Ethics Statement

The research reported is theoretical and hence has not involved any animals.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Mondal, P. Mental Structures as Biosemiotic Constraints on the Functions of Non-human (Neuro)Cognitive Systems. Biosemiotics 13, 385–410 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12304-020-09390-z

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12304-020-09390-z

Keywords

Navigation