Skip to main content
Log in

Steps Towards a Proof-Theoretical Semantics

  • Published:
Topoi Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The aim of this paper is to reconsider several proposals that have been put forward in order to develop a Proof-Theoretical Semantics, from the by now classical neo-verificationist approach provided by D. Prawitz and M. Dummett in the Seventies, to an alternative, more recent approach mainly due to the work of P. Schroeder-Heister and L. Hallnäs, based on clausal definitions. Some other intermediate proposals are very briefly sketched. Particular attention will be given to the role played by the so-called Fundamental Assumption. We claim that whereas, in the neo-verificationist proposal, the condition expressed by that Assumption is necessary to ensure the completeness of the justification procedure (from the outside, so to speak), within the definitional framework it is a built-in feature of the proposal. The latter approach, therefore, appears as an alternative solution to the problem which prompted the neo-verificationists to introduce the Fundamental Assumption.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See Prior (1960).

  2. Important researches in this area, which predates the development of neo-verificationist approach, were developed in the sixties and seventies of the last century by G. Kreisel, N. Goodman, J. Myhill, R. Fagin, and other people. Here, the notion which came to the fore was not “proof”, but the more general notion of “construction”, broadly seen as an open concept, once it is saved its constructivistic flavour.

  3. For details see Schroeder-Heister (2008).

  4. At a certain point, some people rated it necessary to supplement the clause for implication (and the same happened for the clause concerning the universal quantifier): “a construction proving \(\alpha \supset \beta\) is a function f, which maps each construction c proving α to a construction f(c) proving β” with a second clause stating “together with a proof that f has this property”; a move which brings the risk of engendering an infinite series of second clauses.

  5. See for instance Prawitz (1979).

  6. As usual, we indicate with NK and NJ, respectively, the classical and the intuitionistic version of the calculus.

  7. See Prawitz (1965).

  8. The general meaning of the harmony requirement is well expressed by Prawitz in the following passage:

    A lack of harmony would mean that by making an assertion, a person could create false expectations or could commit himself to something that he was unable to fulfil although he had observed the condition for the assertion. When discovered, such a lack of harmony has of course to be mended by changing some of the rules. (see Prawitz 1980).

  9. The second we encounter, after that signalled in Sect. 2.

  10. As it is well known, Dummett is seriously doubtful about the possibility to meet this requirement. In Dummett (1991, 269), for instance, he says that:

    The fundamental assumption is even more essential to the claim of our procedure to justify other laws [different from the self-justifying Introduction rules]. Unsurprisingly, however, what underpin the fundamental assumption are considerations that are not themselves proof-theoretic but are in a broad sense semantic: we are driven to invoke some notion of truth, and so have not achieved a purely proof-theoretic justification procedure.

  11. Whereas the notion of conservative extension was aimed at taking care of the validity of deduction.

  12. For a general discussion of substantial difficulties involved in the Fundamental Assumption see Dummett (1991). For some other comments on this subject, including some critical remarks about suggestions provided by Dummett, see also Moriconi (2000).

  13. See Contu (2006) for interesting remarks on this topic.

  14. See Aczel (1980) and Martin-Löf (1984).

  15. See Lorenzen (1950, 1955).

  16. Where, instead of Gentzen’s sequent-arrow “→” we use “\(\vdash\)”.

  17. See Moriconi (2008), Schroeder-Heister (2007a, b), and Read (2010), where much suitably attention is drawn to some passages from M. Dummett. In fact, he says that

    [There] are two ways of explaining the meanings of the sentenes of a language. In terms of how we establish them as true; and in terms of what is involved in accepting them as true. They are alternative in that either is sufficient to determine the meaning of a sentence uniquely; but they are complementary in that both are needed to give an account of the practice of speaking the language. Because either fully determines the meaning of a sentence [...t]here ought to exists a harmony between these two features of use. (Dummett 1993, 142).

    And then he adds:

    The condition for such harmony to obtain is twofold:first, that whatever serves to justify a statement ought also to justify any simpler statement to which acceptance of the first commit us; and, conversely, that all commitments consequent upon acceptance of a statement should already be consequent upon anything offered in complete justification of it. (Ibid., 162–163).

  18. As usual, we indicate with LK and LJ, respectively, the classical and the intuitionistic version of the sequent calculus.

  19. Gentzen (1932).

  20. See Gentzen (1934, 190).

  21. See Prawitz (1971).

  22. See Hallnäs (1991), Schroeder-Heister (2007a, b).

  23. A substantial enrichment of the expressive power of the framework is obtained by admitting that in the body of definitional clauses implicational formulas might occur; that is, formulas built from atoms by means of a structural implication → to be distinguished from a logical implication \(\supset, \) just like the comma is a structural conjunction which is to be distinguished from ∧. For details see de Campos Sanz and Piecha (2009), Schroeder-Heister (1991, 2007a).

  24. For the sake of simplicity, we do not consider variables, so that we do not have to take care of substitutions of variables.

  25. See Schroeder-Heister (1991).

  26. See for instance Schroeder-Heister (2004) for details.

References

  • Aczel PHG (1980) Frege structures and the notion of proposition, truth and set. In: Barwise J et al (eds) The Kleene symposium. North-Holland, Amsterdam

  • Contu P (2006) The justification of the logical rules revisited. Synthese 148(3):573–588

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Campos Sanz W, Piecha T (2009) Inversion by definitional reflection and the admisibility of logical rules. Rev Symb Log 2(3):550–569

  • Dummett M (1991) The logical basis of metaphysics. Duckworth, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Dummett M (1993) Language and truth. In: The seas of language. Clarendon Press, Oxford, pp 147–65

  • Gentzen G (1932) Über die Existenz unabhängiger Axiomensysteme zu unendlichen Satzsystemen. Math Ann 107:50–329

    Google Scholar 

  • Gentzen G (1934–1935) Untersuchungen über das logische Schliessen. Mathematische Zeitschrift 39:176–210, 405–431. Eng. trans. in Szabo (1969)

    Google Scholar 

  • Hallnäs L (1991) Partial inductive definitions. Theor Comput Sci

  • Lorenzen P (1950) Konstruktive Begründung der Mathematik. Mathematische Zeitschrift 53

  • Lorenzen P (1955) Einfürung in die operative Logik und Mathematik. Springer, Berlin

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin-Löf P (1984) Intuitionistic type theory. Bibliopolis, Napoli

    Google Scholar 

  • Moriconi E (2000) Normalization and meaning theory. Epistemologia XXIII:281–304

    Google Scholar 

  • Moriconi E, Tesconi L (2008) On inversion principles. Hist Philos Log 29(2):103–113

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prawitz D (1965) Natural deduction. Almkvist & Wiksell, Stockholm

    Google Scholar 

  • Prawitz D (1971) Ideas and results in proof theory. In: Fenstad JE (ed) Proceedings of the Second Scandinavian logic symposium. North-Holland, Amsterdam

  • Prawitz D (1979) Proofs and the meaning and completeness of the logical constants. In: Hintikka J et al (eds), Essays on mathematical and philosophical logic. Reidel, Dordrecht

  • Prawitz D (1980) Intuitionistic logic: a philosophical challenge. In: von Wright GH (ed) Logic and philosophy, Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague

    Google Scholar 

  • Prior (1960) The runabout inference-ticket. Analysis 21(2)

  • Read S (2010) General-elimination harmony and the meaning of the logical constants. J Philos Log 39:557--576

    Google Scholar 

  • Schroeder-Heister P (1991) Hypothetical reasoning and definitional reflection in logic programming. In: Schroeder-Heister P (ed) Extensions of logic programming, number 475 in Springer LNAI. Springer, pp 327–339

  • Schroeder-Heister P (2004) On the notion of assumption in logical systems. In: Bluhm R, Nimtz C (eds) Selected papers contributed to the sections of GAP.5, fifth international congress of the society for analytical philosophy, Mentis, Padeborn, pp 27–48

  • Schroeder-Heister P (2007a) Generalized definitional reflection and the inversion principle. Logica Universalis 1(2):355–376

    Google Scholar 

  • Schroeder-Heister P (2007b) Lorenzens operative Logik und moderne beweistheorethische Semantik. In: Mittelstraß J (ed) Der Konstruktivismus in der Philosophie im Ausgang von Wilhelm Kamlah und Paul Lorenzen. Mentis, Padeborn

  • Schroeder-Heister P (2008) Proof-theoretic versus model-theoretic consequence. The Logica yearbook 2007, Prague

  • Szabo MZ (ed) (1969) The collected papers of G. Gentzen. North-Holland, Amsterdam

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I thank Luca Tranchini for helpful comments on a first draft of the paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Enrico Moriconi.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Moriconi, E. Steps Towards a Proof-Theoretical Semantics. Topoi 31, 67–75 (2012). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-012-9120-4

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-012-9120-4

Keywords

Navigation