Skip to main content
Log in

Equilibria with vector-valued utilities and preference information. The analysis of a mixed duopoly

  • Published:
Theory and Decision Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper deals with the equilibria of games when the agents have multiple objectives and, therefore, their utilities cannot be represented by a single value, but by a vector containing the various dimensions of the utility. Our approach allows the incorporation of partial information about the preferences of the agents into the model, and permits the identification of the set of equilibria in accordance with this information. We also propose an additional conservative criterion which can be applied in this framework in order to predict the results of interaction. The potential application of the theoretical results is shown with an analysis of a mixed oligopoly in which the agents value additional objectives other than their own benefit. These objectives are related to social welfare and to the profit of the industry. The flexibility of our approach provides a general theoretical framework for the analysis of a wide range of strategic economic models.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For instance, a sufficient condition for the two sets to coincide is that the sets \(A^i\) are non-empty convex subsets of a finite dimensional space, and the functions \(u_j^i\) are strictly concave in \(a^i\).

  2. Other representations of this objective exist. However, this form is convenient for our analysis.

References

  • Aumann, R. (1962). Utility theory without the completeness axiom. Econometrica, 30, 445–462.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bade, S. (2005). Nash equilibrium in games with incomplete preferences. Economic Theory, 26, 309–332.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bewley, T. (1986). Knightian utility theory: Part 1. Cowles Foundation Discussion Paper 807.

  • Blackwell, D. (1956). An analog of the minimax theorem for vector payoffs. Pacific Journal of Mathematics, 6, 1–8.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Borm, P. E. M., Tijs, S. H., & Van Den Aarssen, J. C. M. (1988). Pareto equilibria in multiobjective games. Methods of Operations Research, 60, 303–312.

    Google Scholar 

  • Corley, H. W. (1985). Games with vector payoffs. Journal of Optimization Theory and Applications, 47, 491–498.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Fraja, G., & Del Bono, F. (1989). Alternative strategies of a public enterprise in oligopoly. Oxford Economic Papers, 41, 302–331.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Fraja, G., & Del Bono, F. (1990). Game theoretic models of mixed oligopoly. Journal of Economic Surveys, 4, 1–7.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dubra, J., Maccheroni, F., & Ok, E. (2004). Expected utility theory without the completeness axiom. Journal of Economic Theory, 115, 118–133.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilboa, I., & Schmeidler, D. (1989). Maxmin expected utility with non-unique prior. Journal of Mathematical Economics, 18, 141–153.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keeney, R. L., & Raiffa, H. (1976). Decisions with multiple objectives: Preferences and value tradeoffs. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kozhan, R., & Salmon, M. (2009). Uncertainty aversion in a heterogeneous agent model of foreign exchange rate formation. Journal of Economic Dynamics & Control, 33, 1106–1122.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kreps, D. M., & Scheinkman, J. A. (1983). Quantity precommitment and Bertrand competition yield Cournot outcomes. The Bell Journal of Economics, 14, 326–337.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Merrill, W., & Schneider, N. (1966). Government firms in oligopoly industries: A short run analysis. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 80, 400–12.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nash, J. (1951). Non-cooperative games. Annals of Mathematics, 54(2), 286–295.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ok, E. A. (2002). Utility representation of an incomplete preference relation. Journal of Economic Theory, 104, 429–449.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Park, J. (2015). Potential games with incomplete preferences. Journal of Mathematical Economics, 61, 58–66.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Patriche, M. (2014). Existence of equilibrium for multiobjective games in abstract convex spaces. Mathematical Reports, 16, 243–252.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sagi, J. S. (2006). Anchored preference relations. Journal of Economic Theory, 13(1), 283–295.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shafer, W., & Sonnenschein, H. (1975). Equilibrium in abstract economies without ordered preferences. Journal of Mathematical Economics, 2, 345–348.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapley, L. S. (1959). Equilibrium points in games with vector payoffs. Naval Research Logistics Quarterly, 6(1), 57–61.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Voorneveld, M., Vermeulen, D., & Borm, P. (1999). Axiomatizations of Pareto equilibria in multicriteria games. Games and Economic Behavior, 28, 146–154.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wakker, P. (2001). Testing and characterizing properties of nonadditive measures through violations of the sure-thing principle. Econometrica, 69(4), 1039–1059.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wald, A. (1950). Statistical decision functions. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wang, S. Y. (1993). Existence of Pareto equilibrium. Journal of Optimization Theory and Applications, 79, 373–384.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zeleny, M. (1975). Games with multiple payoff. International Journal of Game Theory, 4(4), 179–191.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zhao, J. (1991). The equilibria of multiple objective games. The International Journal of Game Theory, 20, 171–182.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

The research of the authors is partially supported by the Spanish Ministry of Economy and Competitiveness, Project ECO2015-68856-P   (MINECO/FEDER) .

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Amparo M. Mármol.

Appendix

Appendix

Proof of Theorem 2.3

First, note that under the assumptions, all the values \(r_j^i(a^{-i})\) are well-defined. Let \(a\in \times _{i\in N}A^i\) be a profile of strategies such that for a certain \(i\in N, a^i< {\underline{r}}^i(a^{-i})\). Since \(u_j^i\) is strictly concave in its own action, then at \(a^i, u_j^i\) is strictly increasing for all \(j\in J^i\), and by adopting a strategy \(a^i+\varepsilon \), with \(\varepsilon >0\), agent i will increase all the components of his utility. Therefore, a is not an equilibrium. Analogous reasoning can be applied when \(a^i >\bar{r}^i(a^{-i})\). Let \(a\in \times _{i\in N}A^i\), such that \({\underline{r}}^i(a^{-i})\le a^i\le {\bar{r}}^i(a^{-i})\) for all \(i\in N\). For \(i\in N\), if \({\underline{r}}^i(a^{-i})= a^i= \bar{r}^i(a^{-i})\), by moving from his strategy, all the components of the utility of agent i will decrease. If \({\underline{r}}^i(a^{-i})< a^i< {\bar{r}}^i(a^{-i})\), at least one of the inequalities in \({\underline{r}}^i(a^{-i})\le a^i\le \bar{r}^i(a^{-i})\) must be strict. If \({\underline{r}}^i(a^{-i})< a^i\), by reducing \(a^i\), the utility corresponding to \({\bar{r}}^i\) will decrease. If \(a^i< {\bar{r}}^i(a^{-i})\), by increasing \(a^i\), the utility corresponding to \({\underline{r}}^i\) will decrease.

Proof of Theorem 2.5

A first inclusion is proved in Wang (1993). Conversely, let \(a^*\in E^w(G)\). For \(i\in N\), define the sets \(Y^i=\{ x\in \mathbb {R}^{s^i} : u^i(a^i, a^{*-i})\geqq x, \, \text{ for } \text{ some } \, a^i\in A^i\}\), and \(X^i=\{ x\in \mathbb {R}^{s^i} : u^i(a^{*})<x\}\). The sets \(Y^i\) and \(X^i\) are convex and disjoint. Convexity is a consequence of the concavity of \(u^i\). To prove that they are disjoint: If \(x\in Y^i\) then \(a^i\in A^i\) exists such that \(x\leqq u^i(a^i, a^{*-i})\). If \(x\in X^i\) then \(x>u^i(a^*)\). Therefore, if \(x\in Y^i\cap X^i\), then \(u^i(a^*)<x\leqq u^i(a^i, a^{*-i})\), and \(a^i\in A^i\) exists with \(u^i(a^*)< u^i(a^i, a^{*-i})\), which contradicts \(a^*\) being a weak equilibrium of G. It follows from Minkowski’s separating hyperplane theorem that there exists some non-null vector \(\lambda ^i\in \mathbb {R}^{s^i}\) and some constant c such that \(\lambda ^i \cdot x\le c\) for all \(x\in Y^i\), and \(\lambda ^i \cdot x\ge c\) for all \(x\in X^i\). It is easy to see that a non-negative \(\lambda ^i\) and \(c=\lambda ^i\cdot u^i(a^*)\) satisfy this condition. Therefore, for each \(i\in N, \lambda ^i\cdot u^i(a^*)\ge \lambda ^i\cdot x\) for all \(x\in Y^i\), and since \(u^i(a^i, a^{*-i})\in Y^i\), for all \(a^i\in A^i, a^{*i}\) maximizes \(v_{\lambda }^i(a^i, a^{*-i})\). Since only the direction of the vector matters, \(\lambda ^i\) can be taken in \(\Delta ^{s^i}\). It follows that \(a^*\in E(G_\lambda )\).

Proof of Proposition 3.2

If \(a^* \in E_{\Lambda }(G)\), then for each \(i \in N\) there exists \(\lambda ^i \in \Lambda ^i\) such that \(a^*\) is an equilibrium of game \(G_{\lambda }\). It follows from Definition 3.1 that \( \lambda ^i\cdot u^i(a^{*})\ge \lambda ^i \cdot u^i (a^{i}, a^{*-i})\), for all \( a^i \in A^i\). On the other hand, for each \( i \in N, \lambda ^i \in \Lambda ^i\) can be written as a convex combination of the extreme points of \(\Lambda ^i, \lambda ^i= \sum _{r=1}^{ p^i}\alpha ^i_r {\bar{\lambda }}^i(r)\) with \(\alpha ^i_r\ge 0\), and \(\sum _{r=1}^{ p^i} \alpha ^i_r=1\). Thus, for each \(i \in N, \sum _{r=1}^{ p^i}\alpha ^i_r{\bar{\lambda }}^i(r)\cdot u^i( a^{*})\ge \sum _{r=1}^{ p^i}\alpha ^i_r {\bar{\lambda }}^i(r)\cdot u^i (a^i, a^{*-i})\) for all \(a^i\in A^i\). It follows that \(a^*\) is a weak equilibrium of game \(\{(A^i, v^i_{\Lambda })_{i \in N}\}\).

Proof of Theorem 3.3

A first inclusion is stated in Proposition 3.2. Conversely, first note that, if for each \(i, u^i\) is concave in \(a^i\), then, \(v_{\Lambda }^i\) is also concave. Let \(a^*\) be a weak equilibrium of game \(\{(A^i, v^i_{\Lambda })_{i \in N}\}\). It follows from Theorem 2.5 that for each \(i\in N, \alpha ^i\in \Delta ^{p^i}\) exists such that \(\sum _{r=1}^{ p^i}\alpha ^i_r{\bar{\lambda }}^i(r)\cdot u^i( a^{*})\ge \sum _{r=1}^{ p^i}\alpha ^i_r {\bar{\lambda }}^i(r)\cdot u^i (a^i, a^{*-i})\) for all \(a^i\in A^i\). Since \(\sum _{r=1}^{ p^i}\alpha ^i_r{\bar{\lambda }}^i(r)\in \Lambda ^i\), from Definition 3.1 it follows that \(a^* \in E_{\Lambda }(G)\).

Proof of Proposition 3.5

Let \( a^*\in E^c_{\Lambda }(G)\) with \(\Lambda = \times _{i\in N}\Lambda ^i\). Thus, \(\not \exists i\in N\) with \( a^i\in A^i \) such that \(\min _{r=1,\ldots ,{p^i}} \{ v^i_{{\bar{\lambda }}(r)}(a^i, a^{*-i}) \} > \min _{r=1,\ldots ,{p^i}} \{ v^i_{{\bar{\lambda }}(r)} ( a^{*}) \} \), where \({\bar{\lambda }}^i(r), r=1,\ldots ,p^i \) are the extreme points of \(\Lambda ^i\). Suppose on the contrary that \(a^*\not \in E_{\Lambda }(G)\). Under convexity assumptions, by Theorem 3.3, \(E_{\Lambda }(G)=E^w(G_{\Lambda })\). Hence, \( a^*\) is not a weak equilibrium of the game \(\{(A^i, v_\Lambda ^i)_{i\in N}\}\). That is, \(\exists i\in N\) with \(a^i\in A^i \) such that \(v^i_{\Lambda }(a^i, a^{*-i}) > v^i_{\Lambda }( a^{*})\). The components of \(v_\Lambda ^i\) are \(v^i_{{\bar{\lambda }}(r)}\) for \(i=1,\ldots , p^i\), and therefore \(v^i_{{\bar{\lambda }}(r)}(a^i, a^{*-i}) > v^i_{{\bar{\lambda }}(r)} ( a^{*}), \forall r=1,\ldots ,p^i\). It follows that \(\min _{r=1,\ldots ,{p^i}} \{v^i_{{\bar{\lambda }}(r)}(a^i, a^{*-i})\}> \min _{r=1,\ldots ,{p^i}} \{v^i_{{\bar{\lambda }}(r)} ( a^{*})\}\), and this contradicts that \( a^*\) is a conservative equilibrium for the game with preference information \(\Lambda \).

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Mármol, A.M., Monroy, L., Caraballo, M.Á. et al. Equilibria with vector-valued utilities and preference information. The analysis of a mixed duopoly. Theory Decis 83, 365–383 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11238-017-9595-y

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11238-017-9595-y

Keywords

Navigation