Skip to main content
Log in

Disagreement, peerhood, and three paradoxes of Conciliationism

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Conciliatory theories of disagreement require that one lower one’s confidence in a belief in the face of disagreement from an epistemic peer. One question about which people might disagree is who should qualify as an epistemic peer and who should not. But when putative epistemic peers disagree about epistemic peerhood itself, then Conciliationism makes contradictory demands and paradoxes arise.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. E.g., Christensen (2007, 2009, 2013); Elga (2007); Feldman (2006, 2007); Kornblith (2010).

  2. The term “epistemic peer” is due to Gutting (1982).

  3. Cf.Kelly (2005): “Let us say that two individuals are epistemic peers with respect to some question if and only if they satisfy the following two conditions: (i) they are equals with respect to their familiarity with the evidence and arguments which bear on that question, and (ii) they are equals with respect to general epistemic virtues such as intelligence, thoughtfulness, and freedom from bias.” (pp. 174–175).

  4. In addition to Gelfert’s informative analysis of epistemic peerhood, see Konigsberg (2013) for a consideration of whether the definition of epistemic peerhood remains constant across domains.

  5. The specifics here will depend on the individual Conciliatory theory and the degrees of confidence that we hold in our beliefs. These specifics are irrelevant for the arguments that I give in this paper.

  6. Belief (5) could be put more precisely but more awkwardly as “I believe that Richard is my epistemic peer with respect to Francis is my epistemic peer with respect to p.” For reasons of economy, I abbreviate this by simply saying that Richard is my epistemic peer with respect to “peerhood assessment”. Here are two interesting questions related to assessments of epistemic peer relationships which I will not explore in this paper: First, is Richard is my epistemic peer simpliciter with respect to my epistemic peer relationships, or is his peer status contingent upon the content of the underlying \(p\)? That is, if Richard is capable of judging who my epistemic peers are with respect to, say, auto repair, is he capable of judging who my epistemic peers are in all domains? Second: How much does Richard have to know about \(p\) to be able to judge my epistemic peer relationships with respect to \(p\)? Can Richard judge who my epistemic peers are with respect to the disagreement debate if Richard does not know any epistemology?

  7. I thank two anonymous reviewers for suggesting this approach to me.

  8. Christensen gives a detailed analysis of higher-order evidence in his 2010.

  9. I happen to be doubtful of the higher-order evidence approach. I’m especially doubtful of the idea that my own psychological response to some first-order evidence \(E\) about \(p\) could count as additional evidence about \(p\); that is, evidence above and beyond \(E\). Cf.Kelly (2010), p. 129.

  10. I thank an anonymous reviewer for several helpful comments along these lines.

  11. The problem of regress is even more acute if it is the case that once I qualify someone as an epistemic peer with respect to some peerhood assessment, I perforce qualify him as an epistemic peer with respect to all my peerhood assessments (see n. 6), or if, as I will discuss in Sect. 4, epistemic peerhood satisfies a closure principle.

  12. This example is due to Feldman (2007).

  13. Bruce Brower raised this question to me.

  14. To put it explicitly, I regard Jimmy as my epistemic peer on both \(p\) and peerhood assessment. It would be unusual—but by no means impossible—to regard someone as a peer on, say, a theoretical moral matter but not as a peer on assessing peerhood.

  15. The nice term “epistemic modesty” is due to Christensen (2013).

  16. Pittard (manuscript) argues that although Elga’s defense of Conciliationism fails, we can remain resolute about our theory, and thus avoid the danger of self-defeat, by distinguishing conciliation at the epistemic level of credence from conciliation at the level of reasoning.

References

  • Christensen, D. (2007). Epistemology of disagreement: The good news. Philosophical Review, 116, 187–217.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Christensen, D. (2009). Disagreement as evidence: The epistemology of controversy. Philosophy Compass, 4, 756–767.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Christensen, D. (2010). Higher-order evidence. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 81, 185–215.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Christensen, D. (2011). Disagreement, question-begging and epistemic self-criticism. Philosophers’ Im-print, 11, 1–22.

  • Christensen, D. (2013). Epistemic modesty defended. In D. Christensen & J. Lackey (Eds.), The epistemology of disagreement: New essays (pp. 77–97). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Elga, A. (2007). Reflection and disagreement. Noûs, 41, 478–502.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elga, A. (2010). How to disagree about how to disagree. In R. Feldman & T. A. Warfield (Eds.), Disagreement (pp. 175–186). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Feldman, R. (2006). Epistemological puzzles about disagreement. In S. Hetherington (Ed.), Epistemology futures (pp. 216–236). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feldman, R. (2007). Reasonable religious disagreements. In L. M. Antony (Ed.), Philosophers without gods: Meditations on atheism and the secular life (pp. 194–214). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gelfert, A. (2011). Who is an epistemic peer? Logos & Episteme, 2, 507–514.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gutting, G. (1982). Religious belief and religious skepticism. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelly, T. (2005). The epistemic significance of disagreement. In T. S. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Oxford studies in epistemology (Vol. 1, pp. 167–196). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelly, T. (2010). Peer disagreement and higher-order evidence. In R. Feldman & T. A. Warfield (Eds.), Disagreement (pp. 111–174). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kelly, T. (2013). Disagreement and the burdens of judgment. In D. Christensen & J. Lackey (Eds.), The epistemology of disagreement: New essays (pp. 31–53). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Konigsberg, A. (2013). The problem with uniform solutions to peer disagreement. Theoria, 79, 96–126.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kornblith, H. (2010). Belief in the face of controversy. In R. Feldman & T. A. Warfield (Eds.), Disagreement (pp. 29–52). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lackey, J. (2010). A justificationist view of disagreement’s epistemic significance. In A. Haddock, A. Millar, & D. Pritchard (Eds.), Social epistemology (pp. 298–325). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lord, E. (2014). From independence to conciliationism: An obituary. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 92, 365–377.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pittard, J. (manuscript). Resolute conciliationism. Retrieved 28 Aug 2014 from http://www.johnpittard.com/John_Pittard/Research_files/Pittard.%20Resolute%20Conciliationism.pdf.

  • Sosa, E. (2010). The epistemology of disagreement. In A. Haddock, A. Millar, & D. Pritchard (Eds.), Social epistemology (pp. 278–297). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I am indebted to Bruce Brower, who, in the autumn of 2013, led the Tulane seminar on disagreement in which these ideas first took shape, and who weighed in on earlier drafts of this paper. I also thank Nathan Biebel and Jesse Hill for their thoughtful criticisms, and three anonymous reviewers, each of whom provided helpful comments which improved this work. I also wish to acknowledge, with gratitude, financial support provided by the Edward Marshall Ballard Memorial Fund and Tulane’s School of Liberal Arts.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Thomas Mulligan.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Mulligan, T. Disagreement, peerhood, and three paradoxes of Conciliationism. Synthese 192, 67–78 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-014-0553-8

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-014-0553-8

Keywords

Navigation