Skip to main content
Log in

Epistemic values and the value of learning

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In addition to purely practical values, there are cognitive values which figure in scientific deliberations. One way of introducing cognitive values is to consider the cognitive value that accrues to the act of accepting a hypothesis. Although such values may have a role to play in the matter of theory acceptance, this does not exhaust their significance in scientific decision-making. This paper makes a plea for the consideration of epistemic value—cognitive value that attaches to a state of belief. I defend the notion of cognitive epistemic value against criticisms that have been raised against it. A stability requirement for epistemic value-functions is argued for on the basis of considerations of diachronic coherence. This requirement is sufficient for proving the Value of Learning Theorem, which says that the expected utility of cost-free learning cannot be negative. Under the assumption of stability, the expected cognitive epistemic value of undergoing a learning experience must also be non-negative.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Brier G. W. (1950) Verification of forecasts expressed in terms of probability. Monthly Weather Review 78: 1–3

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Douglas H. (2000) Inductive risk and values in science. Philosophy of Science 67: 559–579

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Earman J. (1992) Bayes or bust? A critical examination of Bayesian confirmation theory. The MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Fallis D. (2007) Attitudes toward epistemic risk and the value of experiments. Studia Logica 86: 215–246

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frankish K. (2004) Partial belief and flat-out belief. In: Huber F., Schmidt-Petri C. (eds) Degrees of belief: An anthology. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 75–93

    Google Scholar 

  • Good I. J. (1952) Rational decisions. Journal of the Royal Statistical Society, Series B 14: 107–114

    Google Scholar 

  • Good I. J. (1967) On the principle of total evidence. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 17: 319–322

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Good, I. J. (1973). Information, rewards, and quasi-utilities. In J. Leach, R. Butts, & G. Pearce (Eds.), Science, decision, and Value. Western Ontario Series in the Philosophy of Science, Vol. 1 (pp. 115–127). Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing Company.

  • Graves P. R. (1989) The total evidence theorem for probability kinematics. Philosophy of Science 56: 317–324

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greaves H., Wallace D. (2006) Justifying conditionalization: Conditionalization maximizes expected epistemic utility. Mind 115: 607–632

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. G. (1965). Science and human values. In Aspects of scientific explanation (pp. 81–96). New York: Macmillan Publishing Co.

  • Hempel, C. G. (1981). Turns in the evolution of the problem of induction. Synthese, 46, 389–404. Reprinted in J. H. Fetzer (Ed.), The philosophy of Carl G. Hempel. Oxford University Press, 2001, pp. 344–371.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horwich P. (1982) Probability and evidence. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Jeffrey, R. (1956). Valuation and acceptance of scientific hypotheses. Philosophy of Science, 23, 237–246. Reprinted in Probability and the art of judgment. Cambridge University Press, 2002, pp. 14–29.

  • Joyce J. (1998) A nonpragmatic vindication of probabilism. Philosophy of Science 65: 575–603

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn T. S. (1977). Objectivity, value judgment, and theory choice. In The essential tension (pp. 320–339). Chicago, IL: The University of Chicago Press.

  • Levi I. (1967) Gambling with truth: An essay on induction and the aims of science. The MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Longino H. (1995) Gender, politics, and the theoretical virtues. Synthese 104: 383–397

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maher P. (1990) Why scientists gather evidence. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 41: 103–119

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maher P. (1993) Betting on theories. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • McCarthy J. (1956) Measures of the value of information. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America 42: 654–655

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oddie G. (1997) Conditionalization, cogency, and cognitive value. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 48: 533–541

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam H. (2002) The collapse of the fact/value dichotomy and other essays. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Rudner R. (1953) The scientist qua scientist makes value judgments. Philosophy of Science 20: 1–6

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sargent M. (2009) Answering the Bayesian challenge. Erkenntnis 70: 237–252

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Savage, L. J. (1971). Elicitation of personal probabilities and expectations. Journal of the American Statistical Association, 66, 783–801. Reprinted in H. E. Kyburg & H. E. Smokler (Eds.), Studies in subjective probability. Robert E. Krieger Publishing Company, 1980, pp. 149–191

    Google Scholar 

  • Skyrms B. (1990) The dynamics of rational deliberation. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Teller P. (1973) Conditionalization and observation. Synthese 26: 218–258

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen B. (1984) Belief and the will. Journal of Philosophy 81: 235–256

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Wayne C. Myrvold.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Myrvold, W.C. Epistemic values and the value of learning. Synthese 187, 547–568 (2012). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-010-9860-x

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-010-9860-x

Keywords

Navigation