Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-mp689 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-18T02:51:11.048Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Model Selection, Simplicity, and Scientific Inference

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2022

William L. Harper*
Affiliation:
University of Western Ontario
*
Send requests for reprints to the authors, Department of Philosophy, University of Western Ontario, London, ON N6A 3K7, Canada; Myrvold: wmyrvold@uwo.ca; Harper: wlharp@uwo.ca.

Abstract

The Akaike Information Criterion can be a valuable tool of scientific inference. This statistic, or any other statistical method for that matter, cannot, however, be the whole of scientific methodology. In this paper some of the limitations of Akaikean statistical methods are discussed. It is argued that the full import of empirical evidence is realized only by adopting a richer ideal of empirical success than predictive accuracy, and that the ability of a theory to turn phenomena into accurate, agreeing measurements of causally relevant parameters contributes to the evidential support of the theory. This is illustrated by Newton's argument from orbital phenomena to the inverse-square law of gravitation.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Brackenridge, J. B. (1995), The Key to Newton’s Dynamics. Los Angeles: University of California Press.Google Scholar
French, A. P. (1971), Newtonian Mechanics. New York: W.W. Norton & Company.Google Scholar
Forster, Malcolm (2000), “Key Concepts in Model Selection: Performance and Generalizability”, Key Concepts in Model Selection: Performance and Generalizability 44:205231.Google ScholarPubMed
Forster, M., and Sober, E. (1994), “How to Tell When Simpler, More Unified, or Less Ad Hoc Theories Will Provide More Accurate Predictions”, How to Tell When Simpler, More Unified, or Less Ad Hoc Theories Will Provide More Accurate Predictions 45:135.Google Scholar
Harper, W. L. (1997), “Isaac Newton on Empirical Success and Scientific Method,” in Earman, L. and Norton, J. D. (eds.), The Cosmos of Science (Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press), 5586.Google Scholar
Harper, W. L. (1998), “Measurement and Approximation: Newton’s Inferences from Phenomena verses Glymour’s Bootstrap Confirmation” in Weingartner, G., Schurz, G., and Dorn, G. (eds.), The Role of Pragmatics in Contemporary Philosophy. Vienna: Hölder-Pichler-Tempsky, 205287.Google Scholar
Harper, W. L. (1999), “The First Six Propositions in Newton’s Argument for Universal Gravitation”, The First Six Propositions in Newton’s Argument for Universal Gravitation 45 (2): 7493..Google Scholar
Harper, W. L. (forthcoming), “Newton’s Argument for Universal Gravitation,” in Cohen, I. B. and Smith, G. E. (eds.), Cambridge Companion to Newton. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Harper, W. L., Valluri, S. R., and Mann, R. (forthcoming), “Jupiter’s Moons and the Equivalence Principle”, Proceedings of the Ninth Marcel Grossmann Meeting on General Relativity.Google Scholar
Kieseppä, I. A. (1997), “Akaike Information Criterion, Curve-fitting, and the Philosophical Problem of Simplicity”, Akaike Information Criterion, Curve-fitting, and the Philosophical Problem of Simplicity 48:2148.Google Scholar
Linhart, H., and Zucchini, W. (1986), Model Selection. New York: John Wiley & Sons.Google Scholar
Newcomb, S. (1895), The Elements of the Four Inner Planets and the Fundamental Constants of Astronomy. Washington: Government Printing Office.Google Scholar
Newton, Isaac (1999), The Principia: Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy. Translated by Cohen, I. B. and Whitman, A.. Los Angeles: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Sakamoto, Y., Ishiguro, M., and Kitagwa, G. (1986), Akaike Information Criterion Statistics. Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing Company.Google Scholar
Seidelmann, P. K. (ed.) (1992), Explanatory Supplement to the Astronomical Almanac. Mill Valley: University Science Books.Google Scholar
Sober, Elliott (2001), “Instrumentalism, Parsimony, and the Akaike Framework”, Philosophy of Science (Supplement).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stein, H. (1970), “On the Notion of Field in Newton, Maxwell, and Beyond”, in Stuewer, R. H. (ed.), Historical and Philosophical Perspectives of Science. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 264287.Google Scholar
Stein, H. (1991), “‘From the Phenomena of Motions to the Forces of Nature’: Hypothesis or Deduction?”, PSA 1990, Vol. 2. East Lansing, Mich.: Philosophy of Science Association, 209222.Google Scholar
Taton, R., and Wilson, C. (eds.) (1995), The General History of Astronomy, 2B. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Will, C. M. (1993), Theory and Experiment in Gravitational Physics, 2nd revised ed. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zucchini, Walter (2000), “An Introduction to Model Selection”, An Introduction to Model Selection 44:4161.Google ScholarPubMed