Skip to main content
Log in

Why Philosophers should do Semantics (and a bit of syntax too): a Reply to Cappelen

  • Published:
Review of Philosophy and Psychology Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper, I address a series of arguments recently put forward by Cappelen Review of Philosophy and Psychology 8(4): 743–762 (2017) to the effect that philosophers should not do formal semantics or be concerned with the “minutiae of natural language semantics”. He offers two paths for accessing his ideas. I argue that his arguments fail in favour of the first and cast some doubt on the second in so doing. I then proffer an alternative conception of why exactly philosophers should continue to do formal linguistics which includes both semantics and syntax.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Throughout, I will use “formal semantics” and “natural language semantics” interchangeably, although there is a sense in which the latter can be used to refer to a number of semantic frameworks including distributional approaches. This latter meaning, however, is not the sense in which Cappelen (2017) uses the term.

  2. Williamson’s “arguments” include historical reflection, case study, sociological claims as to what philosophers take to be their subject matter, and the alleged failure of the language-centric model in characterising the latter parts of twentieth century analytic philosophy.

  3. David Albert is a case of an academic who publishes in both physics and philosophy journals on related work.

  4. See his Causation, Prediction and Search (2001) for detailed prediction algorithms designed for feasible implementation among other things.

  5. One might of course argue that using data from psychology or linguistics is not the same thing as doing psychology or linguistics. True enough but there are cases where this distinction collapses, especially in linguistics. For example, the analysis of counterfactuals are notoriously sensitive to both distributional (linguistic) and philosophical analysis.

  6. Unfortunately, the consensus ends here and alternative accounts abound. See Szabó (2012) for an account of this principle in terms of inference to the best explanation.

  7. Here again, the philosophy of language dovetails with the research agenda in linguistics where generative grammars were initially designed to find answers to the syntactic side of this puzzle (see Chomsky 2000).

  8. Although it must be noted that Frege was the first to advocate the principle of compositionality (and relatedly the “context principle”) for reference. See Frege (1892, 1919) in particular.

  9. “The Linguistic Turn provided the only good reasons for thinking that philosophy of language was a significant part of philosophy” (Cappelen, 2017: 748).

  10. A more careful characterisation of Williamson’s position would perhaps describe it as the claim that although attention to language and thought might be required for the analysis of philosophical problems, it is ultimately facts about the world, not language, which resolves them. At other points (see chapter 2 of Williamson (2007)) he argues that taking problems at “face-value” is incompatible with taking the linguistic turn.

  11. Cappelen (2017: 748) has an interesting analogy in support of his division of labour argument. He suggests that the case for semantics is analogous to admitting papers on phonology or the “syntax of Romanian” into philosophy journals. If philosophers are reluctant to do the latter then surely papers on the semantics of definites and indefinites in English are equally unwelcome. Two points are worth mentioning. Firstly, definites and indefinites are canonical cases of linguistic expressions with ontological import. Secondly, and more to the point, there are examples of interesting papers on the syntax of specific languages which had significant philosophical impact. Shieber (1985) (published in Linguistics and Philosophy) derived a proof from the structure of Swiss-German to the conclusion that natural language cannot be context-free (or captured by a context-free grammar). Everett (2005) used the syntax of a little known Amazonian language called Pirahã to dispute the claim that recursion is a universal property of natural language (a view held by most linguists of the generative persuasion). One reason these papers on the syntax of particular languages are important to philosophy might have to do with Universal Grammar or the idea that individual languages shed light on our common cognitive endowment (see Chomsky 2000). Thus, these topics certainly seem philosophically significant and in my view it would constitute an omission to banish them from philosophy journals.

  12. Of course, one could make similar arguments in favour of including formal pragmatics within philosophical methodology. Although this task is beyond the current remit, I think it is an acceptable consequence of the arguments in the present paper. In fact, semantics itself can be more broadly construed to include pragmatic analysis (for a lively debate concerning related claims, see Racanati (2003) and Cappelen and Lepore (2005). I thank an anonymous referee for suggesting this connection and consequence to me.

  13. There might be another reason for including syntax in philosophy related to compositionality or the proper relationship between syntax and semantics.

  14. Here the claim is not that philosophy uses results from these theories but actually applies the tools to its analysis such as conditional probabilities to the analysis of credence levels in epistemology.

  15. Here I make a distinction between direct and indirect piecemeal significance. The former can affect the outcome/conclusion of an argument as to the nature of time, or the compositionality of thought etc. while the latter only figures in highly abstract meta-discussions of the practice. I thank an anonymous reviewer for pressing me on this point.

  16. I am grateful to an anonymous reviewer for suggesting this clarification.

  17. For further cases of when language can make a difference to philosophical disputes, see Neta (2012) for epistemology, see Schroeder (2012) for meta-ethics, see Swanson (2012) for causation.

References

  • Boroditsky, L. 2003. Linguistic relativity. In Encyclopedia of cognitive science, ed. L. Nadel. London: Nature Publishing Group.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cappelen, H. 2017. Why philosophers should not do semantics. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, Vol. 8 (4): 743–762.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cappelen, H., and E. Lepore. 2005. Insensitive semantics: a defense of semantic minimalism and speech act pluralism. Hoboken: Blackwell Publishing Ltd..

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. 2000. The architecture of language. New Delhi: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cowie, F. 1999. What’s within: nativism reconsidered. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cullen, S. 2010. Survey-driven romanticism. Review of Philosophy and Psychology 1 (2): 275–296.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. 1965. Theories of meaning and learnable languages. In Inquiries into truth and interpretation, ed. D. Patterson, 3–16. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. 1967. The logical form of action sentences. In The logic of decision and action, ed. N. Rescher, 81–95. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Everett, D. 2005. Cultural constraints on grammar and cognition in Pirahã: another look at the design features of human language. Current Anthropology 46: 621–634.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J., and E. Lepore. 2002. Compositionality papers. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. 1892. On concept and object. Vierteljahrsschrift fur¨ wissenschaftliche Philosophie, 16: 192–205. Trans. Peter Geach, 1952, Translations from the Philosophical Writings of Gottlob Frege, Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 42–55. Reprinted in Frege 1984: 182–194.

  • Frege, G. 1919. Notes for Ludwig Darmstaedter. (Logik in der Mathematik), in Frege 1979: 253–257.

  • Friedenberg, J., and G. Silverman. 2006. Cognitive science: an introduction to the study of mind. Thousand Oaks: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gómez, J., V. Kersken, D. Ball, and A. Seed. 2017. Knowing without knowing: implicit cognition and the minds of infants and animals. Studies in Psychology 38 (1): 37–62.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hansson, S. 2000. Formalization in philosophy. The Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 6 (2): 162–175.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. 1999. Moral philosophy and linguistics. The Proceedings of the Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy 1: 107–115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heim, I., and A. Kratzer. 1998. Semantics in generative grammar. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Katz, J. 1971. Linguistic philosophy: the underlying reality of language and its philosophical import. London: George Allen and Unwin Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

  • Landman, F. 1991. Structures for semantics. Oxford: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Le Poidevin, R. 1996. Time, tense and topology. The Philosophical Quarterly 46 (185): 467–481.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lepore, E., and J. Pelletier. 2012. Meaning and ontology. Shantz: 399–433.

  • Lewis, D. 1970. General semantics. Synthese 22 (1/2): 18–67.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. 1986. On the plurality of worlds. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing.

  • Mellor, D. 1998. Real time II. London: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Moss, S. 2012. The role of linguistics in the philosophy of language. In The routledge companion to the philosophy of language, ed. D. Graff Fara and G. Russell, 513–524. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neta, R. 2012. Philosophy of language for epistemology. In The Routledge companion to the philosophy of language, ed. D. Graff Fara and G. Russell, 693–704. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Partee, B. 2008. Reflections of a formal semanticist. In Compositionality in Formal Semantics, ed. Partee, B, 1–25. Blackwell Publishing.

  • Partee, B., A. ter Meulen, and R. Wall. 1990. Mathematical methods for linguistics. Netherlands: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pullum, G. 1989. The Great Eskimo vocabulary hoax and other irreverent essays on the study of language. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pullum, G. 2011. On the mathematical foundations of syntactic structures. Journal of Logic, Language and Information 20 (3): 277–296.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pullum, G. 2013. The central question in comparative syntactic metatheory. Mind & Language 28 (4): 492–521.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pullum, G.K. and Barbara C. Scholz. 2001. On the distinction between model-theoretic and generative-enumerative syntactic frameworks. In Philippe de Groote, Glyn Morrill, and Christian Retore,eds. Logical Aspects of Computational Linguistics: 4th International Conference, number 2099 in Lecture Notes in Artificial Intelligence, 17–43. Berlin: Springer Verlag

  • Putnam, H. 1971. The ‘Innateness Hypothesis’ and explanatory models in linguistics. In The philosophy of language, ed. J. Searle, 130–139. London: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Racanati, F. 2003. Literal meaning. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rayo, A. 2007. Ontological commitment. Philosophy Compass 2 (3): 428–444.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schroeder, M. 2012. Philosophy of language for metaethics. In The Routledge companion to the philosophy of language, ed. D. Graff Fara and G. Russell, 705–715. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shieber, S. 1985. Evidence against the context-freeness of natural language. Linguistics and Philosophy 8: 333–343.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spirtes, P., C. Glymour, and R. Scheines. 2001. Causation, prediction, and search. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stanley, J. 2000. Context and logical form. Linguistics and Philosophy 23 (4): 391–434.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stanley, J., and T. Williamson. 2001. Know how. The Journal of Philosophy 98 (8): 411–444.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Swanson, E. 2012. the language of causation. In The Routledge companion to the philosophy of language, ed. D. Graff Fara and G. Russell, 716–728. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Szabó, Z. 2012. The case for compositionality. In The Oxford handbook of compositionality, ed. M. Werning, W. Hinzen, and E. Machery, 47–63. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tomalin, M. 2006. Linguistics and the formal sciences. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. 2007. The philosophy of philosophy. Hoboken: Blackwell Publishing.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Winawer, J., N. Witthoft, M. Frank, L. Wu, A. Wade, and L. Boroditsky. 2007. Russian blues reveal effects of language on color discrimination. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America 104 (19): 7780–7785.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I am grateful to Bob M. Martin, Bernhard Weiss, Jack Richter, Paul Egré and two anonymous reviewers for insightful comments of various drafts of this work.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ryan M. Nefdt.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Nefdt, R.M. Why Philosophers should do Semantics (and a bit of syntax too): a Reply to Cappelen. Rev.Phil.Psych. 10, 243–256 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-018-0396-1

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-018-0396-1

Navigation