Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-4hhp2 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-25T05:37:46.152Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

THE SALUTOGENIC EFFECTS OF AWE TOLD EXISTENTIALLY

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  30 December 2021

Get access

Abstract

Feelings of awe can generate well-being. The typical explanation of this is that an otherwise self-absorbed individual now experiences something so vast that it forges a humble new perspective of self. Self-absorption is replaced by altruistic characteristics that result in a sense of well-being. However, the observations of Martin Heidegger, Jean-Paul Sartre, and Carl Rogers provide an existential framework for understanding the human being in relation to the world and well-being within that framework. And such a framework offers a different perspective on how the experience of awe produces well-being. Existentially understood, incongruence is the anti-thesis of well-being. Incongruence is developed by a hyper-focus on external conditions of worth. Rather than a remedy to self-absorption, the experience of awe offers the remedy of self-absorption, towards congruence. This article will explore key observations by each existentially principled thinker to display this framework in order to comprehend how awe produces well-being within it.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2021. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of The Royal Institute of Philosophy

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Earnshaw, S. (2007) Existentialism: A Guide for the Perplexed (London: Continuum).Google Scholar
Fredrickson, B. L. (1998) ‘What Good are Positive Emotions?', Review of General Psychology 2.3: 300–19.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Fredrickson, B. (2013) ‘Positive Emotions Broaden and Build’, in P., Devine and A., Plant (eds.) Advances in Experimental Social Psychology, vol. 47 (Burlington, MA: Academic Press), 153.Google Scholar
Heidegger, M. (2008) Being and Time (New York: Harper Perennial Modern Classics).Google Scholar
Keltner, D., and Haidt, J. (2003) ‘Approaching Awe, a Moral, Spiritual and Aesthetic Emotion’, Cognition & Emotion 17.2: 297314.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Piff, K., Dietze, , Feinberg, M., Stancato, D. M., and Keltner, D. (2015) ‘Awe, the Small Self, and Prosocial Behavior’, Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 108.6: 883–99.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Rogers, C. (1951) Client-Centered Therapy (London: Robinson).Google Scholar
Rogers, C., and Tillich, (1960) A Dialogue with Carl Rogers and Paul Tillich (Chicago: Saybrook University, 1960).Google Scholar
Rudd, M., Vohs, K. D., and Aaker, J. (2012) ‘Awe Expands People's Perception of Time, Alters Decision Making, and Enhances Well-Being’, Psychological Science 23.10: 1130–6.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sartre, J.-P. (1956) Being and Nothingness: An Essay on Phenomenological Ontology (New York: Philosophical Library).Google Scholar
Schneider, K. (2009) Awakening to Awe: Personal Stories of Profound Transformation (Lanham, MD: Jason Aronson, Inc.).Google Scholar