Skip to main content
Log in

The Role of Kinds in the Semantics of Ceteris Paribus Laws

  • Original Article
  • Published:
Erkenntnis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper investigates the interaction between semantic theories for cp-laws (roughly, laws that hold “all things equal”) and metaphysical theories of kinds in the special sciences. Its central conclusion is that cp-laws concerning kinds behave differently from cp-laws concerning non-kinds: “ravens are black” which concerns the kind corvus corax, behaves differently from from “albino ravens are white” which concerns the non-kind grouping of albino ravens. I argue that this difference is in the first instance logical: the two sorts of cp-laws give rise to different inferential patterns. I draw two further conclusions. The difference in logical behavior poses a severe problem for extant semantic theories of cp-laws, and: we cannot elucidate the distinction between kinds and non-kinds by suggesting that only kinds can appear in laws.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. I qualify the claim in the main text by mentioning “substantial and unobvious background assumptions.” Several semantic theories for cp-statements interpret them as restricted universal generalizations (e.g. Hausman 1992). By adding the premise that an instance falls within the restriction, we can draw a valid conclusion. However, such a restriction is substantial and unobvious.

  2. See, e.g., Earman et al. (2002), Earman and Roberts (1999), Pietroski and Rey (1995), Lange (2002).

  3. See, e.g., Spohn (2012).

  4. A terminological note: when I speak of kinds, I do not just have in mind Lewisian perfectly natural properties (cf. Lewis 1999). As will become clear in the sequel, the distinction between kinds and non-kinds reflected in cp-statements involves a much for liberal understanding of kinds.

  5. Cf. West et al. (1997a).

  6. Cf. Carey (2009).

  7. Cf. Stearns and Hoekstra (2000).

  8. Cf. Smith and Pun (2010).

  9. See Schiffer (1991, 10) and Woodward (2002, 305).

  10. Hüttemann (2014) offers a theory of cp-laws in terms of dispositions. The argument I have just made here can be seen as lending further methodological support for treating ascriptions of dispositions as a theoretically viable subgroup of cp-laws. The two kinds of cp-laws do not exhaust the class of generalizations usually captured under the heading of cp-laws. Idealizations are a third (cf. Reutlinger, 2014, for further discussion).

  11. See, e.g., Nickel (in prep).

  12. Spohn (2002, 354). Cf. also Schurz (2002).

  13. For completeness: the inference from superset to subset does not go through either.

  14. I do not intend kind percolation to entail that there is a single taxonomic hierarchy.kind percolation only holds if the kinds involved do stand in the relevant relationship.

  15. I defend this claim in detail in other work. See Nickel (2008, 2010).

  16. One particularly clear example of this approach is Schurz (2014).

  17. It’s a further question how to account for this in a systematic semantic theory. See Liebesman (2011), Leslie (2007) for discussion.

  18. I develop a semantics that predicts these results in a formally more precise way and motivates them in Nickel (2010).

  19. Cf. Krifka et al. (1995, 11).

  20. Space constraints prevent me from pursuing this point here. For further discussion, see Nickel (in prep, chp. 6).

  21. This is not to say that these theories hold that any predicate can figure in a cp-statement. As with all laws, the predicates in cp-statements cannot be too gruesome without rendering the statement defective. However, among the viable cp-statements, these theories do not distinguish those that concern kinds and those that do not.

  22. See, for example, Schurz (2001, 2011), Woodward (2001, 2003), Mitchell (1997, 2000), and proponents of the hpc conception (such as Boyd 1999, 1992; Kornblith 1993; Wilson et al. 2007). It is also endorsed by Lange (1995, 2000, 2002), Spohn (2002, 2012). An interesting case in this respect is Schrenk (2014). He does not explicitly discuss how important broad statistical coverage is to assessing any given system of laws, so the view can perhaps be developed to be compatible with the rejection of the majority constraints.

  23. This example is taken from Wilson et al. (2007, 211).

  24. See also Matthen (2009), Ereshefsky and Matthen (2005) for further discussion.

  25. It is of course metaphysically impossible for mealworms to instantiate the antecedent of this conditional. But the proponent of the conditional strategy cannot appeal to this fact in order to block the conclusion that it’s characteristic for them that if they are as cognitively developed etc. It is also metaphysically impossible for a female to be male, yet that does not stand in the way of her having the conditional property “if male, then having testes.”

  26. Cf. Dodson (1989).

  27. Schurz (2001) draws a similar contrast in a different context between polyphenic traits and genuine polymorphisms.

  28. LF is meant to be evoke the notion of a logical form, though it’s a technical notion.

  29. See Nickel (in prep).

  30. See for example the proponents of the hpc conception of kinds mentioned in note 22, along with the new mechanists (e.g. Craver 2007, 2009; Machamer et al. 2000) and Strevens (2012). In this volume, the contrast between theories of cp-laws that are connected to mechanisms and theories that are not is represented by Pemberton and Cartwright (2014); Strevens (2014) on the mechanism side, and Roberts (2014) on the non-mechanistic side.

  31. See, for example, Strevens (2012) and Nickel (in prep).

  32. The notion of a kind-derived subgroup is a metaphysical, not a syntactic one. There are kinds that have syntactically complex names, such as Common Raven or Duckbilled platypus, and ice probably doesn’t form a natural kind on its own, though it is syntactically simple.

  33. Such dimensions are more generally determinables of the property at issue. Having two wings lies along the dimension of having some number of wings. Flying lies along the dimension of means of locomotion.

  34. A useful heuristic for evaluating what it takes for m* to be just like m is this. Begin with m, considered as a sequence of causally connected events, states, and background conditions. Do nothing until you need to alter any of the events, states, or background conditions to allow that mechanism to operate in the kind-derived subgroup. Then allow the mechanism to develop further.

  35. This is just an illustrative example. Suitability can take many different forms, even in biological contexts, and certainly beyond.

  36. Nota bene: I take it that ecology can have its own, proprietary complement of kinds, including the hunters and the prey, the migratory animals, and so on. So while it may be false that the animals as a whole form a natural kind within the context of evolutionary biology—they aren’t a species, and it may be that only species are kinds (or kind-like individuals) in evolutionary biology—they may still form a kind for the purposes of ecology. If the animals don’t form a kind, the treatment I provide in the text applies equally to particular species, and by kind-percolation, the property that characterizes species also applies to animals.

  37. Mill (1891/2002, 95). Cf. Quine (1969), Goodman (1983).

  38. See Wilson et al. (2007) for an excellent exposition.

References

  • Boyd, R. N. (1992). Constructivism, realism, and philosophical method. In J. Earman (Ed.), Inference, explanation, and other frustrations (pp. 131–198). Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R. N. (1999). Homeostasis, species, and higher taxa. In R. A. Wilson (Ed.), Species: New interdisciplinary essays (pp. 141–185). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carey, S. (2009). The origin of concepts. Oxford: Oxford UP.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. F. (2007). Explaining the brain: Mechanisms and the mosaic unity of neuroscience. Oxford: Oxford UP.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. F. (2009). Mechanisms and natural kinds. Philosophical Psychology, 22(5), 575–594.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dodson, S. I. (1989). Predator-induced reaction norms. BioScience, 39(7), 447–452.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Earman, J., & Roberts, J. (1999). Ceteris paribus, there is no problem of provisos. Synthese, 118(3), 439–478.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Earman, J., Roberts, J., & Smith, S. (2002). Ceteris paribus lost. Erkenntnis, 57(3), 281–301.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ereshefsky, M., & Matthen, M. (2005). Taxonomy, polymorphism, and history: An introduction to population structure theory. Philosophy of Science, 72(1), 1–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (1991). You can fool some of the people all of the time, everything else being equal; hedged laws and psychological explanations. Mind, 100(1), 19–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goodman, N. (1983). Fact, fiction, and forecast. Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hausman, D. M. (1992). The inexact and separate science of economics. Cambridge: Cambridge UP.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hüttemann, A. (2014). Ceteris paribus laws in physics. Erkenntnis. doi:10.1007/s10670-014-9637-6.

  • Kornblith, H. (1993). Inductive inference and its natural ground. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krifka, M., Pelletier, F. J., Carlson, G. N., ter Meulen, A., Chierchia, G., & Link, G. (1995). Genericity: An introduction. In G. N. Carlson & F. J. Pelletier (Eds.), The generic book (pp. 1–124). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lange, M. (1995). Are there natural laws concerning particular biological species? The Journal of Philosophy, 92(8), 430–451.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lange, M. (2000). Natural laws in scientific practice. Oxford: Oxford UP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lange, M. (2002). Who’s afraid of Ceteris–Paribus laws? Or: How I learned to stop worrying and love them. Erkenntnis, 57(3), 407–423.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leslie, S.-J. (2007). Generics and the structure of the mind. In J. Hawthorne (Ed.), Philosophical perspectives 21, philosophy of mind (pp. 375–403). Malden, MA: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. K. (1999). New work for a theory of universals. In Papers in metaphysics and epistemology (pp. 8–55). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge UP.

  • Liebesman, D. (2011). Simple generics. Noûs, 45(3), 409–442.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lowe, E. (2009). More kinds of being. Malden, MA: Wiley Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Machamer, P. K., Darden, L., & Craver, C. F. (2000). Thinking about mechanisms. Philosophy of Science, 57(1), 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Matthen, M. (2009). Chickens, eggs, and speciation. Noûs, 43(1), 94–115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mill, J. S. (1891/2002). A system of logic: Ratiocinative and inductive, Honolulu: University Press of the Pacific. Reprint of the 1891 edition.

  • Mitchell, S. D. (1997). Pragmatic laws. Philosophy of Science, 64, S468–S479.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell, S. D. (2000). Dimensions of scientific law. Philosophy of Science, 67(2), 242–265.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nickel, B. (2008). Generics and the ways of normality. Linguistics and Philosophy, 31(6), 629–648.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nickel, B. (2010). Generically free choice. Linguistics and Philosophy, 33(6), 479–512.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nickel, B. (in prep) Between logic and the world. Oxford: Oxford UP.

  • Pemberton, J., & Cartwright, N. (2014). Ceteris paribus laws need machines to generate them. Erkenntnis. doi:10.1007/s10670-014-9639-4.

  • Pietroski, P. M., & Rey, G. (1995). When other things aren’t equal: Saving ceteris paribus laws from vacuity. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 46(1), 81–110.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. (1969). Natural kinds. In Ontological relativity and other essays (pp. 114–138). New York: Columbia UP.

  • Reutlinger, A. (2014). Do statistical laws solve the ‘problem of provisos’? Erkenntnis. doi:10.1007/s10670-014-9640-y.

  • Roberts, J. T. (2014). CP-law statements as vague, self-referential, self-locating, statistical, and perfectly in order. Erkenntnis. doi:10.1007/s10670-014-9641-x.

  • Schiffer, S. (1991). Ceteris paribus laws. Mind, 100(1), 1–17.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schrenk, M. (2014). Better best systems and the issue of CP-laws. Erkenntnis. doi:10.1007/s10670-014-9642-9.

  • Schurz, G. (2001). What is ‘normal’? An evolution-theoretic foundation for normic laws and their relation to statistical normality. Philosophy of Science, 68(4), 476–497.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schurz, G. (2002). Ceteris paribus laws: Classification and deconstruction. Erkenntnis, 57(3), 351–372.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schurz, G. (2011). Evolution in Natur und Kultur: Eine Einfürung in the verallgemeinerte Evolutionstheorie. Heidelberg: Spektrum Akademischer Verlag.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schurz, G. (2014). Ceteris paribus and ceteris rectis laws: Content and causal role. Erkenntnis. doi:10.1007/s10670-014-9643-8.

  • Smith, G. A., & Pun, A. (2010). How does earth work? (2nd ed.). New York: Prentice Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spohn, W. (2002). Laws, ceteris paribus conditions, and the dynamics of belief. Erkenntnis, 57(3), 373–394.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spohn, W. (2012). The laws of belief. Oxford: Oxford UP.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stearns, S. C., & Hoekstra, R. F. (2000). Evolution: An introduction. Oxford: Oxford UP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strevens, M. (2012). Ceteris paribus hedges: Causal voodoo that works. Journal of Philosophy, 109(11), 652–675.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strevens, M. (2014). High-level exceptions explained. Erkenntnis. doi:10.1007/s10670-014-9644-7.

  • West, G. B., Brown, J. H., & Enquist, B. J. (1997a). A general model for the origin of allometric scaling laws in biology. Science, 276(5309), 122–126.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • West, G. B., Brown, J. H., & Enquist, B. J. (1997b). A general model for the origin of allometric scaling laws in biology. Science, 276, 122–126.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, R. A., Barker, M. J., & Brigandt, I. (2007). When traditional essentialism fails: Biological natural kinds. Philosophical Topics, 35(1–2), 189–215.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2001). Law and explanation in biology: Invariance is the kind of stability that matters. Philosophy of Science, 68(1), 1–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2002). There is no such thing as a ceteris paribus law. Erkenntnis, 57(3), 303–328.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2003). Making things happen. Oxford: Oxford UP.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Bernhard Nickel.

Additional information

I want to thank the participants of the Workshop on the Semantics and Pragmatics of cp-clauses, where this paper was first presented, as well as the editors of this journal and two anonymous referees.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Nickel, B. The Role of Kinds in the Semantics of Ceteris Paribus Laws. Erkenn 79 (Suppl 10), 1729–1744 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-014-9638-5

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-014-9638-5

Keywords

Navigation