Skip to main content
Log in

Come as you are? Public Reason and Climate Change

  • Published:
Res Publica Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The likely adverse effects of climate change call for political action. In this paper, we argue that the public reason framework—with its insistence on justifiability to all reasonable citizens, in spite of their profound disagreements—despite initial misgivings recommends itself as a framework for debate and decisions pertaining to climate change. We address two possible stumbling blocks: the exclusion of non-anthropocentric points of view, and the controversy over intergenerational justice. We argue that public reason can deal with these problems. Moreover, we argue that both strongly idealized (in Rawls's vein) and moderately idealized (using Gaus as a foil) versions are able to address these issues. Moreover, public reason, as a family of views emphasizing disagreement and justifiability to all reasonable citizens, can help secure the stability of political orders, and hence contribute to sustained and demanding efforts to combat the adverse effects of climate change.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. We follow here the list of assumptions made by Sinnott-Armstrong (Sinnott-Armstrong 2011).

  2. We do not mean that any and all aspects of state action concerning abatement and adaptation need to be seen as fundamental. We only claim that a not-negligible portion of those actions should (and can) be seen as such.

  3. It may be queried whether the distinction between strong and moderate idealization holds in the way we assume, and whether Rawls's project relies on strong idealization. We thank an anonymous referee for pointing this out. First, we admit that idealization comes in degrees, but that there are genuine differences. The juxtaposition of Rawls and Gaus as using ‘strong’ and ‘moderate’ has precedents in the literature (Quong 2017; see also Vallier 2019, pp. 98ff.). Second, it is arguable that Rawls towards the very end of his career relied less on the Original Position (surely a device of strong idealization) and more on a less idealized Public Reason view, even allowing some degree of pluralism as concerns justice; yet it is also arguable that mainstream Rawlsianism leans more towards the strong idealization view, whereas figures such as Gaus and Vallier should be seen as proponents of a less idealized view. See, e.g., Gaus on Rawls in Gaus (2011, pp. xvii, 38f., 284).

  4. There have been several attempts to align Rawls and climate change action. However, we have found no papers that directly addresses the public reason dimension of Rawls's work and climate change as we do here. Also, many have criticized Rawls's programme for being unable to adequately deal with the challenges of climate change, viz. Bell (2004), Buchanan (2000), Gardiner (2011a).

  5. There are of course other ways of showing that Rawlsian theory without modifications is up to the task. Sarah Kenehan presents an interesting defence of the robustness of the duty of assistance in this regard.

  6. For a thorough and critical account of the evolution of Rawls's thoughts on this account see Heyd (2009).

  7. This is admittedly vague. Gaus does not demand of deliberators that they are highly sophisticated, ‘post-conventional’ (Kohlbergian stage 5 or 6) reasoners (Gaus 2011, p. 277).

  8. We thank an anonymous referee for this and the following point.

  9. As a final line of thought, Gaus’s framework may be compatible with climate action on grounds of non-interference: If adverse effects of climate change can be construed as (illegitimate) interference, then the members of the public would be justified in pursuing policies to mitigate or even cancel out these effects. We are thankful for an anonymous referee for this suggestion, but for reasons of space we cannot pursue it further here; see, however, e.g., Gaus (2011 pp. 341ff.).

References

  • Bell, D.R. 2004. Environmental refugees: What rights? Which duties? Res Publica 10: 135–152.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bell, D.R. 2006. Political liberalism and ecological justice. Analyse & Kritik 28: 206–222.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Benn, S. 1988. A theory of freedom. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, A. 2000. Rawls’s law of peoples: Rules for a vanished westphalian world. Ethics 110 (4): 697–721.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Calder, G. 2011. Climate change and normativity: Constructivism versus realism. Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 14: 153–169.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cudd, A., and S. Eftekhari. 2017. “Contractarianism”. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/contractarianism/. Accessed 6 May 2021.

  • Dobson, Andrew. 1998. Justice and the environment: Conceptions of environmental sustainability and theories of distributive justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gardiner, Stephen M. 2011a. Rawls and climate change: Does Rawlsian political philosophy pass the global test? Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 14: 125–151.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gardiner, Stephen M. 2011b. A perfect moral storm: The ethical tragedy of climate change. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gaus, G. 2011. The order of public reason: A theory of freedom and morality in a diverse and bounded world. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gaus, G. 2015. Public reason liberalism. In The Cambridge Companion to Liberalism, ed. S. Wall, 112-140. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139942478.008.

  • Heyd, D. 2009. A value or an obligation? Rawls on justice to future generations. In Intergenerational justice, ed. A. Gosseries, and L.H. Meyer, 167–188. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kunnas, J. 2012. The theory of justice in a warming climate. Electronic Green Journal. https://doi.org/10.5070/G313412180.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Larmore, C. 2003. Public reason. In The Cambridge Companion to Rawls, ed. S.R. Freeman, 368–393. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lister, M. 2011. The order of public reason: A theory of freedom and morality in a diverse and bounded world. Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews.

  • Manning, R. 1981. Environmental ethics and Rawls’ theory of justice. Environmental Ethics 3 (3): 155–165.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peffer, R.G. 2014. Marxism, morality, and social justice. Berlin, Boston: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quong, J. 2010. Liberalism without perfection. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Quong, J. 2017. Public Reason. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/public-reason/. Accessed 8 Jan 2021.

  • Rawls, J. 1993. Political liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. 1997. The idea of public reason revisited. The University of Chicago Law Review 64 (3): 765–807. https://doi.org/10.2307/1600311.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. 2001. Collected papers. Edited by Samuel Richard Freeman. 4. printing. New York: Harvard University Press.

  • Rawls, J. 2005. A theory of justice. Original. Cambridge: Belknap Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz, J. 1994. Facing diversity: The case of epistemic abstinence. In Ethics in the public domain, ed. J. Raz. London: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sinnott-Armstrong, W. 2011. It's not my fault. In Gardiner et al 2010, Climate ethics: Essential readings. Oxford: Oxford University Press

  • Stern, N. 2011. The economics of climate change. In Gardiner et al. 2010, Climate ethics: Essential readings. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Vallier, K. 2019. Must politics be war? Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wallack, M. 2006. Justice between generations: The limits of procedural justice. In Handbook of intergenerational justice, ed. Jörg. Tremmel, 86–105. Cheltenham: Elgar.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wenar, L. 2008. John Rawls. In The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/rawls/. Accessed 7 May 2021.

  • Wolf, C. 2009. Intergenerational justice, human needs and human rights. In Intergenerational justice, ed. Axel Gosseries and Lukas H. Meyer. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

The authors would like to thank the practical philosophy research group at Copenhagen University and the anonymous referees at Res Publica.

Funding

No funding.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Morten Ebbe Juul Nielsen.

Ethics declarations

Conflicts of interest

The authors declare that they have no competing interests.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Nielsen, M.E.J., Hauge-Helgestad, A. Come as you are? Public Reason and Climate Change. Res Publica 28, 17–32 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11158-021-09517-0

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11158-021-09517-0

Keywords

Navigation