Skip to main content
Log in

The Evolutionary Thought of Jean-Baptiste Lamarck

Why His Original Ideas Should Be Taught in Classrooms

  • Article
  • Published:
Science & Education Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The name Lamarck is very well known in the teaching of biology, being associated with an early effort to explain evolution. Nevertheless, when evolution is taught in the classroom, the only Lamarckian ideas that stand out are related to the ‘inheritance of acquired characters’, invariably illustrated by the example of the lengthening of giraffes’ necks, as a way of contrasting Lamarckian ideas with Darwinian natural selection. Our aim here is to argue that there are other important ideas in Lamarck’s work that are directly related to the origin and transformation of species. These concepts, causal explanations of organic nature, can be taught to students who are learning about the sources and development of evolutionary thought and will moreover provide the student with properly justified reasons as to why Lamarck’s explanation is considered to be the first wide-ranging and well-argued explanation of biological evolution. The Lamarckian concepts that we consider important for teaching evolutionary thought are the following: (1) the species as an arbitrary concept, directly related to the Lamarckian concept of the continuous transformation of species, (2) the ancestor–descendant relationship, and organic diversification from a common plan of organisation to a branching series, (3) gradual change, related to changes in environmental conditions, and (4) the controversy concerning the origin of life (that is, having either a natural cause or a divine origin), life’s transformation, and the natural origin of human beings, including our moral capacity, subjects which were related to Lamarck’s other political and philosophical interests.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. References and quotations were consulted in Philosophie zoologique, in the University of Granada’s digital library: Volume I: https://digibug.ugr.es/handle/10481/7712 and Volume II: https://digibug.ugr.es/handle/10481/7711

  2. On the discussion of the translation of ‘besoin’ as desire instead of ‘need’, see for instance Cannon, 1957; Mayr 1972. In translations into other languages, for example Spanish, ‘besoin’ has been correctly translated from the French. See Lamarck, 2017.

  3. ‘C’est surtout dans les corps vivans, et principalement dans les animaux, qu’on a cru apercevoir un but aux opérations de la nature. Ce but cependant n’y est là, comme ailleurs, qu’une simple apparence et non une réalité’ (Lamarck, 1815, T. I., p. 324).

  4. ‘Adaptation’ was not a word used by Lamarck.

  5. It is important to note that for Lamarck ‘natural’ means ‘material’. That is, he explains natural phenomena in terms of material causes. On the varieties of naturalism in historical terms, see Harrison and Roberts, 2019, 1–6.

  6. This avoids continually repeating a story with the same authors, and it can be shown that scientific practice is much more complex in terms of its development, construction of knowledge, and the complex relationships established between different actors in the same scientific community.

  7. In the closing decades of the nineteenth century and at the beginning of the twentieth, Lamarck’s ideas were widely known in academic settings in various countries, in parallel with the introduction, dissemination, and appropriation of Darwinism (Glick, 2010; Glick et al., 2001). With the emergence of the Modern synthesis, Lamarck’s ideas were reduced to an example of an incorrect scientific explanation and, while it was recognised by the authors of the synthesis that Lamarck’s contributions were broader than simply the notion of inheritance of acquired characters, his notions of inheritance and evolution were already outdated and were downgraded to a marginal status (Dobzhansky, 1942, 392), no more than a scientific anecdote. Dobzhansky’s position was more or less similar to that taken in various English-speaking countries, though not in others where Lamarck continued to figure centrally in biology textbooks, sharing credit with Darwin for ideas about the inheritance of acquired characters (Todes, 1989). In the former Soviet Union and other socialist countries, it was practically compulsory for a Marxist to adopt the ideas of the inheritance of acquired characters (Gaissinovitch, 1980, 6), in an environment that Zirkle (1959) and other authors referred to as ‘Marxist biology’. Under the influence of Russian biology, even at the height of the synthetic theory, the durability of the idea of inheritance of acquired characters as a valid scientific explanation was evident in textbooks that were prepared for biology teaching until almost the nineteen-sixties (Argueta Villamar et al., 2003).

  8. ‘Ainsi, cette Philosophie zoologique présent les résultats de mes études sur les animaux, leurs caractères généraux et particuliers, leur organisation, les causes de ses développemens et de sa diversité, et facultés qu´ils en obtiennent;’ (Lamarck, 1809a, 1809b, T. I, p. viii). [Thus, this Zoological Philosophy presents the results of my studies on animals, their general and particular characters, their organisation, the causes of their development and diversity, and the faculties they obtain from it;].

  9. Lyell attempted to refute this idea in the Principles of Geology (Lyell 1832). On Lyell’s evolutionism, see for example Coleman (1962) and Recker (1990).

  10. On Lamarck, irritability and sentience see Giglioni, 2013.

  11. Lamarck assumes that there is no spontaneous generation of organisms per se but of organised matter having present certain properties of life, such as irritability and reproduction, forms that would later give rise to organisms in the full sense of the word (Lamarck, 1802, pp. 36–37).

  12. See for example Coffin (1917) and Polowetzky (1993).

  13. On the issue of morality, the French philosopher Pierre Jean George Cabanis is a strong influence (1757–1808), in particular, Rapports du physique et du moral de l’homme (1802).

References

  • Almeida, A. V. D., & Falcão, J. T. D. R. (2010). As teorias de Lamarck e Darwin nos livros didáticos de Biologia no Brasil. Ciência & Educação (Bauru), 16(3), 649–665.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Álvarez Pérez, E., & Ruiz Gutiérrez, R. (2016). Proposal for teaching evolutionary biology: A bridge between research and educational practice. Journal of Biological Education, 50(2), 123–146.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Andreasen, R. O. (2007). Biological conceptions of race. In M. Matthen & C. Stephens (Eds.), Philosophy of biology: Handbook of the philosophy of science (pp. 455–481). Elsevier.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Argueta Villamar, A., Noguera, R., Ruiz, G., & R. . (2003). La recepción del lysenkismo en México. Asclepio, 55(1), 235–262.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ausubel, D. P. (1966). An evaluation of the BSCS approach to high school biology. The American Biology Teacher, 28(3), 176–186.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ayala, F. J., & Arp, R. (Eds.). (2010). Contemporary debates in philosophy of biology. Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blom, P. (2011). A wicked company: The forgotten radicalism of the European enlightenment. McClelland & Stewart.

    Google Scholar 

  • Browne, B. (2011). Charles Darwin: The power of place. Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buffon, G. L. L. (1749). Histoire Naturelle: Histoire générale des Animaux, Histoire naturelle de l’Homme. Imprimerie royale.

  • Burkhardt, R. W. (1972). The inspiration of Lamarck’s belief in evolution. Journal of the History of Biology, 5(2), 413–438.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cabanis, P. J. G. (1802). Rapports du physique et du moral de l’homme. Caille et Ravier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Charles Lyell to Charles Darwin, March 15, 1863. Darwin Correspondence Project, ‘Letter no. 4041’. Accessed on 24 Sep 2020, https://www.darwinproject.ac.uk/letter/DCP-LETT-4041.xml.

  • Cannon, H. G. (1957). What Lamarck really said. Proceedings of the Linnaean Society of London, 168, 70–87.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coffin, V. (1917). Censorship and literature under Napoleon I. The American Historical Review, 22(2), 288–308.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coleman, W. (1962). Lyell and the reality of species: 1830–1833. Isis, 53, 325–338.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Corsi, P. (1987). After the revolution: Scientific language and French politics, 1795–1802. Nuncius, 2, 89–144.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Corsi, P. (2006). Biologie. In P. Corsi, J. Gayon, G. Gohau, & S. Tirard (Eds.), Lamarck, philosophe de la nature (pp. 37–64). Presses Universitaires de France.

    Google Scholar 

  • Corsi, P. (2011). Jean-Baptiste Lamarck: From myth to history. In Gissis, S., Gissis, S. B., & Jablonka, E. (Eds.). Transformations of Lamarckism: From subtle fluids to molecular biology (9–20). MIT press.

  • Corsi, P. (2012). Idola Tribus: Lamarck, politics and religion in the early nineteenth century. In A. Fasolo (Ed.), The theory of evolution and its impact (pp. 11–39). Springer-Verlag Italia.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • D’Holbach, P. H. T. B. (2010). Superstition in all ages. Knoop, Anna (trad). Lulu. com.

  • Dobzhansky, T. (1942). Biological adaptation. The Scientific Monthly, 55(5), 391–402.

    Google Scholar 

  • Enderle, P. J., Smith, M. U., & Southerland, S. (2009). Does prior knowledge matter? Do Lamarckian misconceptions exist? A critique of Geraedts and Boersma. International Journal of Science Education, 31(18), 2527–2532.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fouad, K. E., Masters, H., & Akerson, V. L. (2015). Using history of science to teach nature of science to elementary students. Science & Education, 24(9–10), 1103–1140.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gaissinovitch, A. E. (1980). The origins of Soviet genetics and the struggle with Lamarckism, 1922–1929. Journal of the History of Biology, 13(1), 1–51.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Giglioni, G. (2013). Jean-Baptiste Lamarck and the place of irritability in the history of life and death. In S. Normandin & Ch. Wolfe (Eds.), Vitalism and the scientific image in post-enlightenment life science, 1800–2010 (pp. 19–49). Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gillispie, Ch. C. (1958). Lamarck and Darwin in the history of science. American Scientist., 46(4), 388–409.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ginsburg, S., & Jablonka, E. (2019). The evolution of the sensitive soul: Learning and the origins of consciousness. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Glick, T. F., & Kohn, D. (Eds.). (1996). On evolution: The development of the theory of natural selection. Hackett Publishing Company Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glick, T. F. (2010). The comparative reception of Darwinism: A brief history. Science & Education, 19(6–8), 693–703.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glick, T. F., Puig-Samper, M. A., & Ruiz, R. (Eds.). (2001) The reception of Darwinism in the Iberian world: Spain, Spanish America and Brazil (Vol. 221). Springer Science & Business Media.

  • Harrison, P., & Roberts, J. H. (Eds.). (2019). Science without God? Rethinking the history of scientific naturalism. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hodge, M. J. S. (1971). Lamarck’s science of living bodies. The British Journal for the History of Science, 5(4), 323–352.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hull, D. (2014). Darwinism as an historical entity: A historiographic proposal. In D. Kohn (Ed.), The Darwinian heritage (pp. 773–812). Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jablonka, E., & Lamb, M. J. (2014). Evolution in four dimensions, revised edition: Genetic, epigenetic, behavioral, and symbolic variation in the history of life. MIT press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Jensen, M. S., & Finley, F. N. (1995). Teaching evolution using historical arguments in a conceptual change strategy. Science Education, 79(2), 147–166.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jensen, M. S., & Finley, F. N. (1996). Changes in students’ understanding of evolution resulting from different curricular and instructional strategies. Journal of Research in Science Teaching: The Official Journal of the National Association for Research in Science Teaching, 33(8), 879–900.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jiménez-Aleixandre, M. P. J. (1994). Teaching evolution and natural selection: A look at textbooks and teachers. Journal of Research in Science Teaching, 31(5), 519–535.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jiménez-Aleixandre, M. P. (1996). Darwinian and Lamarckian models used by students and its representation. Knowledge acquisition organization and use in biology. Dordrecht, 65–77.

  • Kampourakis, K., & Zogza, V. (2007). Students’ preconceptions about evolution: How accurate is the characterization as ‘Lamarckian’ when considering the history of evolutionary thought? Science & Education, 16(3–5), 393–422.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kampourakis, K. (Ed.). (2013). The philosophy of biology: A companion for educators. Springer Science & Business Media.

  • Kampourakis, K., & Nehm, R. H. (2014) History and philosophy of science and the teaching of evolution: Students’ conceptions and explanations. In International handbook of research in history, philosophy and science teaching (pp. 377–399). Springer.

  • Kutschera, U. (2011). From the scala naturae to the symbiogenetic and dynamic tree of life. Biology direct, 6(1), 33.R.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lamarck, J. B. (1794). Recherches sur les causes des principaux faits physiques, tome premier. Maradan.

  • Lamarck, J. B., (1802). Recherches sur l’organisation des corps vivans, et particulièrement sur son origine, sur la cause de ses développemens et des progrès de sa composition… : l’an X de la République. Chez l’auteur, au Muséum d’histoire naturelle.

  • Lamarck, J. B. (1809a). Philosophie zoologique, ou exposition des considérations relatives à l’histoire naturelle des animaux. Tome premier. Dentu. https://digibug.ugr.es/handle/10481/7712‘‘ https://digibug.ugr.es/handle/10481/7712.

  • Lamarck, J. B. (1809b). Philosophie zoologique, ou exposition des considérations relatives à l’histoire naturelle des animaux. Tome second. Dentu. https://digibug.ugr.es/handle/10481/7711.

  • Lamarck, J. B. (1820). Système analytique des connaissances positives de l’homme. Chez l’Auteur et Belin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lamarck, J. B. (1914). Zoological philosophy: An exposition with regard to the natural history of animals. Hugh Elliot, trans., Macmillan and Co., Ltd.

  • Lamarck, J. B. (1815). Histoire naturelle des animaux sans vertèbres, Tome premier, Paris: Vèrdiere, Libraire. Disponible en: https://archive.org/search.php?query=Lamarck.

  • Lamarck, J. B. (2017). Filosofía zoológica. La Oveja Roja.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lyell, C. (1832). Principles of Geology (Vol. 2). John Murray.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthews, M. R. (1989). A role for history and philosophy in science teaching. Interchange, 20(2), 3–15.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mayr, E. (1972). Lamarck revisited. Journal of the History of Biology, 55–94.

  • Mayr, E. (2002). The biology of race and the concept of equality. Daedalus, 131(1), 89–94.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meslier, J. (1864) [1733]. Le testament. V. 1 Georg Olms Verlag.

  • McComas, W. F. (2008). Seeking historical examples to illustrate key aspects of the nature of science. Science & Education, 17, 249–263.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Numbers, R. L., & Kampourakis, K. (Eds.). (2015). Newton’s apple and other myths about science. Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Onfray, M. (2007). Les Ultras des Lumières, contre-histoire de la philosophie. Grasset & Fasquelle.

    Google Scholar 

  • Panchen, A. L. (1992). Classification, evolution, and the nature of biology. University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pigliucci, M., & Kaplan, J. (2003). On the concept of biological race and its applicability to humans. Philosophy of Science, 70(5), 1161–1172.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Poiani, A. (Ed.). (2012). Pragmatic evolution: Applications of evolutionary theory. Cambridge University Press.

  • Polowetzky, M. (1993). A bond never broken: The relations between Napoleon and the authors of France. Fairleigh Dickinson Univ Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Radick, G. (2016). Teach students the biology of their time. Nature, 533, 293.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Recker, D. (1990). There’s more than one way to recognize a Darwinian: Lyell’s Darwinism. Philosophy of Science, 57, 459–478.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Settlage, J., Jr. (1994). Conceptions of natural selection: A snapshot of the sense-making process. Journal of Research in Science Teaching, 31(5), 449–457.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sloan, P. R. (1987). From logical universals to historical individuals: Buffon’s idea of biological species. In J. Roger & Fischer, J. L. (Ed.), Histoire du Concept d’Espèce dans les Sciences de la Vie (pp. 101–140). Fondation Singer-Polignac.

  • Tassy, P. (2011). Trees before and after Darwin. Journal of Zoological Systematics and Evolutionary Research, 49(2), 89–101.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Todes, D. P. (1989). Darwin without Malthus: The struggle for existence in Russian evolutionary thought. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilkins, J. S. (2009). Species: A history of the idea. University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zirkle, C. (1959). Evolution, Marxian biology, and the social scene. University of Pennsylvania Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ricardo Noguera-Solano.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of Interest

The authors have no conflicts of interest to declare that are relevant to the content of this article.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Noguera-Solano, R., Rodríguez-Caso, J.M. & Ruiz-Gutiérrez, R. The Evolutionary Thought of Jean-Baptiste Lamarck. Sci & Educ 30, 909–929 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11191-021-00215-0

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11191-021-00215-0

Navigation