Skip to main content
Log in

Hyperintensional metaphysics

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In the last few decades of the twentieth century there was a revolution in metaphysics: the intensional revolution. Many metaphysicians rejected the doctrine, associated with Quine and Davidson, that extensional analyses and theoretical resources were the only acceptable ones. Metaphysicians embraced tools like modal and counterfactual analyses, claims of modal and counterfactual dependence, and entities such as possible worlds and intensionally individuated properties and relations. The twenty-first century is seeing a hypterintensional revolution. Theoretical tools in common use carve more finely than by necessary equivalence: two pieces of language can apply to the same entities across all possible worlds but not be equivalent; thoughts can be necessarily equivalent in truth value but not synonymous. This paper argues that hyperintensional resources are valuable in metaphysics outside theories of representation, and discusses some promising areas of hyperintensional metaphysics.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Braddon-Mitchell, D. (2009). Naturalistic analysis and the a priori. In D. Braddon-Mitchell & R. Nola (Eds.), Conceptual analysis and philosophical naturalism (pp. 23–43). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

  • Cresswell, M. J. (1970). Classical intensional logics. Theoria, 36, 347–372.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cresswell, M. J. (1975). Hyperintensional logic. Studia Logica, 34(1), 25–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1975). Thought and talk. In S. Guttenplan (Ed.), Mind and language. Oxford, Oxfordshire, UK: Oxford University Press.

  • Dunn, J. M. (1990a). Relevant predication 2: Intrinsic properties and internal relations. Philosophical Studies, 60, 117–206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dunn, J. M. (1990b). Relevant predication 3: Essential properties. In J. M. Dunn & A. Gupta (Eds.), Truth or consequence: Essays in honor of Nuel Belnap (pp. 77–95). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Eddon, M. (2011). Intrinsicality and hyperintensionality. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 82, 314–336.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fine, K. (1994). Essence and modality. Philosophical Perspectives, 8, 1–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fine, K. (2012). Guide to ground. In F. Correia & B. Schnieder (Eds.), Metaphysical grounding (pp. 37–80). Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hintikka, J. (1962). Knowledge and belief. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jenkins, C. S. (2011). Is metaphysical dependence irreflexive? The Monist, 94(2), 267–276.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jenkins, C. S., & Nolan, D. (2012). Disposition impossible. Noûs, 46(4), 732–753.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jespersen, B. (2010). How hyper are hyperpropositions? Language and Linguistics Compass, 4(2), 96–106.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. (1980). Naming and necessity. Oxford, Oxfordshire, UK: Basil Blackwell.

  • Lewis, D. (1973). Counterfactuals. Oxford, Oxfordshire, UK: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1983). New work for a theory of universals. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 61, 343–377.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1986). On the plurality of worlds. Oxford, Oxfordshire, UK: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Montague, R. (1969). On the nature of certain philosophical entities. The Monist, 53(2), 159–194.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Montague, R. (1970). Pragmatics and intensional logic. Synthese, 22, 68–94.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nolan, D. (1997). Impossible worlds: A modest approach. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 38(4), 535–572.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Partee, B. H. (1973). The semantics of belief sentences. In K. J. J. Hintikka, J. M. E. Moravcsik, & P. Suppes (Eds.), Approaches to natural languages. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W.V. (1953) Three grades of modal involvement reprinted in Quine, W.V. (1966). The ways of paradox (pp. 156–174). New York: Random House.

  • Quine, W.V. (1956) Quantifiers and propositional attitudes reprinted in Quine, W.V. (1966). The ways of paradox (pp. 183–194). New York: Random House.

  • Schaffer, J. (2009). On what grounds what. In D. J. Chalmers, D. Manley, & R. Wasserman (Eds.), Metametaphysics (pp. 347–383). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schnieder, B. (2011). A logic for ‘because’. The Review of Symbolic Logic, 4(3), 445–465.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R. (1968). A theory of conditionals. In N. Rescher (Ed.), Studies in logical theory American philosophical monograph series, no. 2 (pp. 98–112). Oxford, Oxfordshire, UK: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tichy, P. (1988). The foundations of Frege’s logic. Berlin: De Gruyter.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

Thanks to Alex Sandgren and audiences at the 2013 Pacific APA in San Francisco and the 2013 AAP in Brisbane for useful feedback.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Daniel Nolan.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Nolan, D. Hyperintensional metaphysics. Philos Stud 171, 149–160 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-013-0251-2

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-013-0251-2

Keywords

Navigation