Skip to main content
Log in

Ditching determination and dependence: or, how to wear the crazy trousersa

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper defends Flatland—the view that there exist neither determination nor dependence relations, and that everything is therefore fundamental—from the objection from explanatory inefficacy. According to that objection, Flatland is unattractive because it is unable to explain either the appearance as of there being determination relations, or the appearance as of there being dependence relations. We show how the Flatlander can meet the first challenge by offering four strategies—reducing, eliminating, untangling and omnizing—which, jointly, explain the appearance as of determination relations where no such relations obtain. Since, plausibly, dependence relations just are asymmetric determination relations, we argue that once we come mistakenly to believe that there exist determination relations, the existence of other asymmetries (conceptual and temporal) explains why it appears that there are dependence relations.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The view owes its name to Bennett (2011). See also her (2017).

  2. Or, alternatively (perhaps), that everything that exists is neither fundamental nor non-fundamental.

  3. See Schaffer (2009), Cameron (2008), Audi (2012), Rodriguez-Pereyra (2015) and Raven (2012) for discussions of ground thought of as a dependence relation. Perhaps all synchronic dependence relations are relations of ground, or perhaps there are some such relations that are not relations of ground. Nothing we say hangs on this.

  4. One could choose to use terminology differently: some think that some instances of modal relations—namely the non-symmetric instances—are dependence relations. Nothing hangs on our use of terminology here.

  5. Also sometimes known as grounding claims.

  6. Indeed, many so-called operationalists about grounding take the view that grounding claims are properly regimented in terms of a sentential operator. [See Fine (2012), Correia (2005), Dasgupta (2014) and Litland (2013)]. Operationalists see grounding as a non-truth-functional sentential connective, which takes arguments/sentences on either side. Operationalists often remain neutral about the truth conditions for such claims. Others have attempted to provide truth conditions that do not appeal to dependence relations.

  7. Norton and Miller (2017) defend a view of roughly this kind.

  8. See Fine (1994b) and Barnes (2018).

  9. See Schnieder (2006).

  10. See Liggins (2016).

  11. Van Inwagen (1990) and Merricks (2001) apply this strategy, though only selectively. Both deny the existence of most ordinary composite objects (like tables and chairs).

  12. Though note that identity is understood in non-standard ways on some of these views (e.g., Baxter 1988a, b) and therefore may or may not be able to do the work required by the Flatlander. See Carrara and Lando (2016) for discussion.

  13. Though see Forrest (2002) and Maddy (1990) for views to the contrary.

  14. Both responses are derived from existing eliminativist explanations for common belief in the existence of eliminated entities. An example of the first strategy is Van Inwagen (1990: pp. 108–114); an example of the second is Merricks (2001: p. 172).

  15. Alternatively, one could maintain that claims in the non-austere language are strictly and literally true, but that they do not (despite appearances) carry any ontological commitment to entities outside of the minimal supervenience base [e.g., Horgan and Potrč (2000, 2006), Azzouni (2017)]. Thanks to an anonymous referee for suggesting this response.

  16. Notice that nothing we say here requires that expressions in the non-austere language mean the same thing as the relevant expressions in the austere language. Our claim is merely that certain austere truths entail certain non-austere truths. At most, it follows that the non-austere expressions have the same truth-values, but it does not follow that they have the same meanings.

  17. In the case of composition, it has been pointed out by Sider (2011: p. 79) and Cameron (2012) that even if composites are identical to their proper parts (jointly) this is not sufficient to explain why the properties of composite objects necessarily co-vary with certain properties of individual proper parts, and so reductionism fails to explain all of the modal covariation. For example, why is it that, necessarily, the location of my right arm is a proper subregion of the location of my whole body? It looks like D-relations are needed to explain this (cf. Cameron 2012: p. 97).

    This is not an objection we can address in detail here. Suffice to say, we do not find it to be anywhere near decisive. Under composition as identity the question of why my right arm (if it is still attached!) must be located at a proper subregion of the location of my body reduces to the question of why my right arm must be located at a proper subregion of where my body parts are collectively located (since my body = my body parts, taken together). And since composition as identity can be applied to locations too, this further reduces to the question of why, necessarily, the location of my right arm is one of the locations of my body parts (since the location of my body = the location of my body parts). But the answer to that question doesn’t seem to us to require D-relations. If my right arm is one of my body parts (by stipulation), and each body part has a location, then it follows analytically that the location of my arm must be one of the locations of my body parts. Insofar as my arm is one of my body parts, then, of necessity, it is located at one of the location of my body parts. Still, clearly more would need to be said here.

  18. See Cameron (2007) for discussion along these lines.

  19. Miller and Norton (2017), for instance, take this to be the principal explanatory task for those who reject Dependence.

  20. Braddon-Mitchell (2017) discusses such a view, as does Price (2007).

References

  • Antony, L. M. (2003). Who’s afraid of disjunctive properties? Philosophical Issues, 13(1), 1–21.

    Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong, D. (1978). Universals and scientific realism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong, D. (1997). A world of states of affairs. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Audi, P. (2012). A clarification and defense of the notion of grounding. In F. Correia & B. Schnieder (Eds.), Metaphysical grounding: Understanding the structure of reality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Azzouni, J. (2017). Ontology without borders. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barnes, E. (2018). Symmetric dependence. In G. Priest & R. Bliss (Eds.), Reality and its structure. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baxter, D. (1988a). Many-one identity. Philosophical Papers, 17(3), 193–216.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baxter, D. (1988b). Identity in the loose and popular sense. Mind, 97, 575–582.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bennett, K. (2011). By our bootstraps. Philosophical Perspectives., 25, 27–41.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bennett, K. (2017). Making things up. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bigelow, J., & Pargetter, R. (1990). Science and necessity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Böhn, E. D. (2009). Composition as identity: A study in ontology and philosophical logic. Doctoral Dissertation, University of Massachusetts Amherst.

  • Boroditsky, L. (2001). Does language shape thought? English and Mandarin speakers’ conceptions of time. Cognitive Psychology, 43, 1–22.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boroditsky, L., Fuhrman, O., & McCormick, K. (2011). Do English and Mandarin speakers think about time differently? Cognition, 118, 123–129.

    Google Scholar 

  • Braddon-Mitchell, D. (2017). The glue of the universe. In H. Beebee & C. Hitchcock (Eds.), Making a difference: Essays on the philosophy of causation. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brenner, A. (2015). Mereological nihilism and theoretical unification. Analytic Philosophy, 56(4), 318–337.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brenner, A. (2017). Mereological nihilism and personal ontology. Philosophical Quarterly, 67(268), 464–485.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cameron, R. (2007). The contingency of composition. Philosophical Studies, 136(1), 99–121.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cameron, R. (2008). Truthmakers and ontological commitment: or how to deal with complex objects and mathematical ontology without getting into trouble. Philosophical Studies, 140, 1–18.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cameron, R. (2012). Composition as identity doesn’t settle the special composition question. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 84(3), 531–554.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carrara, M., & Lando, G. (2016). Composition, indiscernibility, coreferentiality. Erkenntnis, 81(1), 119–142.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. J. (2012). Constructing the world. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D., & Jackson, F. (2001). Conceptual analysis and reductive explanation. Philosophical Review, 110(3), 315–361.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clapp, L. (2001). Disjunctive properties: Multiple realizations. Journal of Philosophy, 98(3), 111–136.

    Google Scholar 

  • Correia, F. (2005). Existential dependence and cognate notions. Munich: Philosophia Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cotnoir, A. J. (2013). Composition as general identity. In K. Bennett & D. W. Zimmerman (Eds.), Oxford studies in metaphysics (Vol. 8, pp. 294–322). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dasgupta, S. (2014). On the plurality of grounds. Philosophers’ Imprint, 14(20), 1–28.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine, K. (1994a). Essence and modality. Philosophical Perspectives, 8, 1–16.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine, K. (1994b). Senses of essence. In W. Sinnott-Armstrong, D. Raffman, & N. Asher (Eds.), Modality, morality and belief. Essays in honor of Ruth Barcan Marcus. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine, K. (2012). Guide to ground. In F. Correia & B. Schnieder (Eds.), Metaphysical grounding: Understanding the structure of reality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Forrest, P. (2002). Sets as mereological tropes. Metaphysica, 3, 5–10.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gillett, C., & Rives, B. (2005). The non-existence of determinables: Or, a world of absolute determinates as default hypothesis. Nous, 39(3), 483–504.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heil, J. (2003). Levels of reality. Ratio, 16(3), 205–221.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horgan, T., & Potrč, M. (2000). Blobjectivism and indirect correspondence. Facta Philosophica, 2, 249–270.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horgan, T., & Potrč, M. (2006). Abundant truth in an austere world. In M. Lynch & P. Greenough (Eds.), Truth and realism: New essays (pp. 137–167). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1971). Counterparts of persons and their bodies. Journal of Philosophy, 68, 203–211.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1983). New work for a theory of universals. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 61(4), 342–377.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1986). On the plurality of worlds. Oxford: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Liggins, D. (2016). Deflationism, conceptual explanation, and the truth asymmetry. Philosophical Quarterly, 66(2), 84–101.

    Google Scholar 

  • Linsky, B., & Zalta, E. (1994). In defense of the simplest quantified modal logic. Philosophical Perspectives, 8, 431–458.

    Google Scholar 

  • Litland, J. E. (2013). On some counterexamples to the transitivity of grounding. Essays in Philosophy, 14, 19–32.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maddy, P. (1990). Realism in mathematics. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Massin, O. (2013). Determinables and brute similarities. In C. Svennerlind, J. Almäng, & R. Ingthorsson (Eds.), Johanssonian investigations: Essays in honour of Ingvar Johansson on his seventieth birthday (pp. 388–420). Heusenstamm: Ontos Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merricks, T. (2001). Objects and persons. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, K., & Norton, J. (2017). Grounding, it’s (probably) all in the head. Philosophical Studies, 174(12), 3059–3081.

    Google Scholar 

  • Noonan, H. (1993). Constitution is identity. Mind, 102, 133–146.

    Google Scholar 

  • Norton, J., & Miller, K. (2017). A psychologistic theory of metaphysical explanation. Synthese. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1566-x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parsons, J. (2013). Conceptual conservatism and contingent composition. Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy, 56(4), 327–339.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pilling, M., Wiggett, A., Ozgen, E., & Davies, I. R. (2003). Is colour “categorical perception” really perceptual? Memory and Cognition, 31(4), 548–551.

    Google Scholar 

  • Price, H. (2007). Causal perspectivalism. In H. Price & R. Corry (Eds.), Causation, physics, and the constitution of reality: Russell’s republic revisited. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1953). Identity, ostension and hypostasis. In W. V. O. Quine (Ed.), From a logical point of view (2nd ed., pp. 65–79). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raven, M. J. (2012). In defence of ground. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 90(4), 687–701.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robertson, D., Davidoff, J., Davies, I. R., & Shapiro, L. R. (2005). Colour categories: Evidence for the cultural relativity hypothesis. Cognitive Psychology, 50, 378–411.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robertson, D., Davies, I., & Davidoff, J. (2000). Color categories are not universal: Replications and new evidence from a stone-age culture. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 129, 396–398.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rodriguez-Pereyra, G. (2002). Resemblance nominalism: A solution to the problem of universals. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rodriguez-Pereyra, G. (2015). Grounding is not a strict order. Journal of the American Philosophical Association, 1(3), 517–534.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saucedo, R. (2011). Parthood and location. In K. Bennett & D. Zimmerman (Eds.), Oxford studies in metaphysics (Vol. 6, pp. 223–284). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J. (2009). On what grounds what. In D. Manley, D. Chalmers, & R. Wasserman (Eds.), Metametaphysics: New essays on the foundations of ontology (pp. 347–383). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schnieder, B. (2006). A certain kind of trinity: Substance, dependence, explanation. Philosophical Studies, 129, 393–419.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sider, T. (2001). Four-dimensionalism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sider, T. (2011). Writing the book of the world. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sider, T. (2013). Against parthood. Oxford Studies in Metaphysics, 8, 237–293.

    Google Scholar 

  • Unger, P. (1979). There are no ordinary things. Synthese, 41, 117–154.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Inwagen, P. (1990). Material beings. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wallace, M. (2011a). Composition as identity: Part 1. Philosophy Compass, 6(11), 804–816.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wallace, M. (2011b). Composition as identity: Part 2. Philosophy Compass, 6(11), 817–827.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, J. R. G. (2007). The possibility of onion worlds: Rebutting an argument for structural universals. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 85(2), 193–203.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2002). Necessary existents. In A. O’Hear (Ed.), Royal institute of philosophy supplement (pp. 233–251). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Winawer, J., Witthoft, N., Frank, M. C., Wu, L., Wade, A. R., & Borodistky, L. (2007). Russian blues reveal effects of language on color discrimination. The National Academy of the Sciences, 104(19), 7780–7785.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

With thanks to Mike Raven, attendees of the 2016 Australian Metaphysics Conference (Kioloa Coastal Campus), members of the weekly supervision group at Sydney University, and to anonymous referees from this and other journals for helpful comments on earlier versions of the paper. Funding was provided by Australian Research Council (Grant No. FT170100262).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Michael Duncan.

Additional information

aKaren Bennett calls the view we consider ‘crazypants’ (Bennett 2011); however, in British English the expression would be ‘crazy trousers’. So we are inclined to wear crazy trousers, not crazy pants (since the latter would require wearing crazy underwear). With special thanks to Jonathan Tallant for suggesting we write a paper defending the wearing of crazy trousers.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Duncan, M., Miller, K. & Norton, J. Ditching determination and dependence: or, how to wear the crazy trousersa. Synthese 198, 395–418 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-02023-6

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-02023-6

Keywords

Navigation