Skip to main content
Log in

Scaffolded practical knowledge: a problem for intellectualism

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Roughly speaking, intellectualists contend that practical knowledge is always a matter of having the right kind of propositional knowledge. This article argues that intellectualism faces a serious explanatory challenge when practical knowledge crucially relies on ecological information, i.e. when know-how is scaffolded. More precisely, intellectualists struggle to provide a satisfactory explanation of seeming know-how contrasts in structurally similar cases of scaffolded ability manifestation. In contrast, even if anti-intellectualism is similarly challenged, at least some varieties of anti-intellectualism seemingly hold resources to account for the relevant contrasts.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Note that here know-how does not comprise all knowledge ascribed by way of the “know how” expression. E.g. to know how Julius Caesar died does not constitute know-how in the practical sense relevant here (Rumfitt 2003: 166).

  2. As Kathrine Hawley has also pointed out, at least for some skills which abilities warrant their ascription varies by context. E.g. in a British context a driver needs to be able to handle a stick transmission for her to be skilled at driving, whereas this is not the case in all American contexts (Hawley 2003: 5–8). More generally, Erasmus of Rotterdam’s famous dictum seems relevant: In regione caecorum rex est luscus (literally “In the region of the blind the sighted man is king” but traditionally rendered in English as: “In the land of the blind, the one-eyed man is king” Knowles ed. 1999: 301). E.g. the lament is typically heard from older people that the range of abilities needed to count as skillful or practically knowledgeable at some traditional task is not as broad as it used to be or as difficult to manifest.

  3. We owe this response to Mona Simion in conversation.

  4. Examples in this style hark not least from Carr 1979. Carr memorably uses the example of a dancer, who is highly competent at performing a particular dance routine, which unbeknownst to him also constitutes a semaphoric rendition of Thomas Gray’s famous Elegy Written in a Country Churchyard (1979: 407). See also Fantl 2008: Sect. 2.

  5. Here we do not want to commit to the controversial thesis that all explanations must be contrastive (famous sources of this thesis are Van Fraassen (1980) and Garfinkel (1981)). Rather, we simply maintain that when the explanatory value of an explanans crucially turns on the otherwise unexplained “inadequacy” of some variable value, only a contrast could satisfactorily account for the explanatory force of this inadequacy.

  6. Of course, it does not follow from there being clear-cut contrasts in know-how that know-how is never gradable. Very plausibly, most types of know-how are indeed gradable (Pavese 2017).

  7. We use the term “subjective nominalism” in accordance with the usage established by D.M. Armstrong (1978: Chapters 2–3), where conceptualists and traditional predicate nominalists equally count as subjective nominalists.

  8. Note that this is not the kind of error-theory we deemed inappropriate in Sect. 3. The subjective nominalist recognizes the contrast in know-how between Chris and Berta/Will but prefers to account for this contrast in subjectivist terms: we ascribers are the measure of the contrast, not the inherent traits of the ascribees. We are grateful to an anonymous referee for this journal for urging us to point this out.

  9. See, however, D’Almeida (2016).

  10. This is not to say that holding Chris responsible is inconsistent with the Chris vignette, only that, unlike the Berta and Will vignettes, the Chris vignette does not afford the ascription of responsibility in any clear way. We are grateful to an anonymous referee for this journal for urging us to make this clear.

  11. Notice that an anti-intellectualist may insist on a close tie (relevant to a context) between a skill and a range of abilities without thereby committing to any specific theoretical account of this relation. But it seems tempting to employ Ernest Sosa’s influential conception of competence as “the disposition (ability) to succeed when one tries” (2015: 95) and then understand skill as the inner seat of such a competence, i.e. that state in virtue of which the agent will ably succeed given favorable external conditions (2010: 465).

  12. Several colleagues have contributed to this article with helpful comments and ideas. Special thanks extend to Kelly Becker, Mikkel Gerken, Chris Kelp, Simon Larsen, Mona Simion, the audience at the 2019 27th Bled Philosophical Conference, arranged by The Slovenian Society for Analytical Philosophy, and an anonymous referee for this journal.

References

  • Armstrong, D. M. (1978). Universals and scientific realism. Volume I: Nominalism and realism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bengson, J., & Moffett, M. A. (2007). Know-how and concept possession. Philosophical Studies, 136, 31–57.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bengson, J., & Moffett, M. A. (2012). Non-Propositional Intellectualism. In J. Bengson & M. A. Moffett (Eds.), Knowing how: Essays on knowledge, mind, and action (pp. 161–195). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bengson, J., Moffett, M. A., & Wright, J. C. (2009). The folk on knowing how. Philosophical Studies, 142(3), 387–401.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brogaard, B. (2008). Knowledge-the and propositional attitude ascriptions. Grazer Philosophische Studien, 77, 147–190.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brogaard, B. (2011). Knowledge-how: A unified account. In J. Bengson & M. A. Moffett (Eds.), Knowing how: Essays on knowledge, mind, and action (pp. 136–160). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carr, D. (1979). The logic of knowing how and ability. Mind, 88, 394–409.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carter, A. J., & Pritchard, D. (2015). Knowledge-how and cognitive achievement. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 91, 181–199.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • D’Almeida, L. D. (2016). Geach and ascriptivism: Beside the point. Journal for The History of Analytical Philosophy, 4(6), 1–17.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dickie, I. (2012). Skill before knowledge. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 85(3), 737–745.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fantl, J. (2008). Knowing-how and knowing-that. Philosophy Compass, 3(3), 451–470.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Farkas, K. (2016). Know-wh does not reduce to know-that. American Philosophical Quarterly, 53, 109–122.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garfinkel, A. (1981). Forms of explanation: Rethinking the questions in social theory. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Geach, P. (1960). Ascriptivism. Philosophical Review, 69(2), 221–225.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glick, E. (2011). Two methodologies for evaluating intellectualism. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 83(2), 398–434.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glick, E. (2012). Abilities and know-how attributions. In J. Brown & M. Gerken (Eds.), Knowledge ascriptions (pp. 120–139). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Habgood-Coote, J. (2019). Knowledge-how, abilities, and questions. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 97(1), 86–104.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hawley, K. (2003). Success and knowledge-how. American Philosophical Quarterly, 40(1), 19–31.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hawley, K. (2010). Testimony and knowing how. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 41, 397–404.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hickman, N. W. (2018). Knowing in the “executive way”: Knowing how, rules, methods, principles and criteria. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. https://doi.org/10.1111/phpr.12488.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knowles, E. (Ed.). (1999). The Oxford book of quotations. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1979). Counterfactual dependence and time’s arrow. NOÛS, 13(4), 455–476.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nozick, R. (1981). Philosophical explanations. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pavese, C. (2016a). Skill in epistemology I: Skill and know how. Philosophy Compass, 11(11), 642–649.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pavese, C. (2016b). Skill in epistemology II: Skill and know how. Philosophy Compass, 11(11), 650–660.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pavese, C. (2017). Know-how and gradability. Philosophical Review, 126(3), 345–383.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rumfitt, I. (2003). Savoir faire. Journal of Philosophy, 100, 158–166.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Snowdon, P. (2004). Knowing how and knowing that: A distinction reconsidered. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 104, 1–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, E. (2010). How competence matters in epistemology. Philosophical Perspectives, 24(1), 465–475.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, E. (2015). Judgment and agency. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stanley, J. (2011). Know how. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stanley, J., & Williamson, T. (2001). Knowing how. Journal of Philosophy, 98, 411–444.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stanley, J., & Williamson, T. (2017). Skill. NOÛS, 51(4), 713–726.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny, K. (2010). Minds: Extended or scaffolded? Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 9, 465–481.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sutton, J. (2010). Exograms and interdisciplinarity: History, the extended mind, and the civilizing process. In R. Menary (Ed.), The Extended Mind (pp. 189–225). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Sutton, J., & Tribble, E. (2011). Cognitive ecology as a framework for shakespearean studies. Shakespeare Studies, 39, 94–103.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tribble, E. (2005). Distributing cognition in the globe. Shakespeare Quarterly, 56, 135–155.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Fraassen, B. (1980). The scientific image. Oxford: The Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Nikolaj Nottelmann.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Nottelmann, N., Thorsson, K. Scaffolded practical knowledge: a problem for intellectualism. Philos Stud 178, 577–595 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-020-01446-7

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-020-01446-7

Keywords

Navigation