Hostname: page-component-7c8c6479df-p566r Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-03-28T19:19:16.726Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Heavy and light in Democritus and Aristotle: two conceptions of change and identity

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  23 December 2013

D. O'Brien
Affiliation:
Centre National de la Recherche Scientifíque, Paris

Extract

Aristotle and Theophrastus are the two major sources for our knowledge of the atomist theory of weight.

In the De generatione et corruptione Aristotle argues that one atom may be hotter than another and that therefore the atoms cannot be impassible, since an atom which is only slightly hot could not fail to be acted upon by an atom that was very much hotter (i 8 325b36–26a14, esp. 326a6–12 = in part DK 68A60). The premiss to the argument Aristotle derives in part from a comparison with weight. It would be ridiculous, he claims, to suppose that hotness and coldness belong to the atoms, but that heaviness and lightness, hardness and softness do not belong to them (326a6–8). And in fact, he continues, Democritus does claim (καίτοι…γε… φησίν) that each of the ‘indivisibles’ is βαρύτερον…κατὰ τὴν ὑπεροχήν (a9–10). Aristotle has already supposed that one kind of atom, a round atom, may be accounted as hot (a3–5). The use of the comparative for weight (βαρύτερον) Aristotle now takes to justify the use of the comparative for heat (θερμότερον a10–11): from this there follows the argument that the atoms cannot be impassible.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Society for the Promotion of Hellenic Studies 1977

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 This article summarises, except for the final section, a much longer study of which the first volume will be published soon in Philosophia Antiqua. The pages on Democritus were read to a session of the Third International Symposium on Ancient Philosophy held at Toledo in the summer of 1974 and presided over by Professor W. J. Verdenius. I am particularly grateful for the criticisms made at the conference by Professor Verdenius and Mr Peter Bicknell. I am also most grateful for their criticisms to Mrs K. M. Burnett, Mme F. Zaslawski and Dr S. V. Keeling. The whole paper has also benefited greatly from a series of lucid and very useful criticisms made by Dr G. E. R. Lloyd. I would emphasise that in this paper I have deliberately set out to present an overall view of a wide range of evidence, consciously leaving aside many of the difficulties which the interpretation of each piece of evidence has given rise to in the past. There is a much more detailed analysis in my longer study of the subject: meanwhile, the simplified treatment of the present version is, I hope, justified by the attempt to provide in a short space a single view of a complex subject which has not hitherto been treated as a whole.

2 Cherniss, H. F., Aristotle's criticism of Presocratic philosophy (Baltimore, 1935) 96100Google Scholar, 209–13, see esp. 211 n. 253 and 97 n. 412.

3 Guthrie, W. K. C., De caelo Loeb, edn (1939)Google Scholar.

4 Cherniss, , ACP 211Google Scholar n. 253. Guthrie, History ii 403 n. 2: the reference to Cherniss in Guthrie's History should be corrected to conform to the reference that I have given.

5 McDiarmid, J. B., ‘Theophrastus De sensibus philology 55 (1960) 2830. 61–62Google Scholar: Democritus', theory of weight’, Classical philology 55 (1960) 2830Google Scholar.

6 Burnet, J., Early Greek philosophy 4th edn (London, 1930) 341–7Google Scholar. Kirk, G. S., The Presocratic philosophers (Cambridge, 1957) 414–16Google Scholar. Guthrie, , History ii 400–4Google Scholar.

7 Zeller, E., Die Philosophie der Griechen i 2 ed. Nestle, W. (Leipzig, 1920) 1068Google Scholar n. 1, cf. 1076–99.

8 Kirk, , Pres. 415Google Scholar. Burnet, , EGP 345Google Scholar n. 1, cf. 343 n. 3. Brieger, A., ‘Die Urbewegung der Demokritischen Atome’, Philologus 63 n. F. 17 (1904) 584–96Google Scholar, see esp. 586, cf. Die Urbewegung der Atome und die Weltentstehung bei Leucipp und Demokrit (Gymnasialprogramm, Halle A/S, 1884). Dyroff, A., Demokritstudien (Leipzig, 1899) 31–9Google Scholar. Zeller, i 2, 1084 = 5th edn i 2 (1892) 876.

9 Taylor, A. E., A commentary on Plato's ‘Timaeus’ (Oxford, 1928) 440–4Google ScholarGoogle Scholar. Martin, T.-H., Études sur le Timée de Platon ii (Paris, 1841) 279–80.

10 P. Moraux (1965) cxlvii.

11 Cherniss, H. F., Aristotle's criticism of Plato and the Academy (Baltimore, 1944) 138–9Google Scholar, 161–5. Solmsen, F. writes of the ‘illuminating analysis’ in Cherniss, Aristotle's system of the physical world (New York, 1960) 280Google Scholar n. 19.

12 Longo, O., Aristotele ‘De caelo’, introduzione etc. (Firenze, 1961)Google Scholar.

13 J. L. Stocks, in the Oxford translation of the works of Aristotle, vol. ii (1930). Guthrie, Loeb edn.

14 Robin, L., La pensée grecque (Paris, 1923) 135–46Google Scholar, see esp. 138.