Skip to main content
Log in

Voices of madness in Foucault and Kierkegaard

  • Article
  • Published:
International Journal for Philosophy of Religion Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The central idea of this paper is that Michel Foucault and Søren Kierkegaard are unexpected allies in the investigation into the relation between madness and reason. These thinkers criticize reason’s presumption of purity and call into question reason’s isolation from madness. Strategies of indirect communication and regard for paradox from Kierkegaard’s nineteenth-century works find new ground in Foucault’s twentieth-century archaeological undertaking as Foucault illuminates “both-and” moments in the history of madness, uncovering points where rationalism paradoxically conceives of madness or where madness is not unreasonable. Furthermore, for both thinkers, form and content meet, as Kierkegaard and Foucault’s occasionally “delirious lyricism” (in the phrase of Dominick LaCapra) exemplifies the intertwining of logical and illogical forces.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Lynne Huffer, who reads the History of Madness as a melodrama, describes such a bid for expression as a matter of betrayal, rather than disturbance. Referencing Foucault’s first preface, she writes, “To speak unreason is to speak in the ‘merciless’ (xxvii) language of reason. To speak unreason is to betray it” (Huffer 2013, p. 639).

  2. Perhaps to the extent that reason and madness are fused, reason can have mad ends and madness can have rational ends.

  3. This phrase may be found in LaCapra (2000, p. 132). See also Felman (1975, pp. 220, 223). For example, “the term madness is itself pathos, not logos; literature, and not philosophy” (Felman 1975, p. 224).

  4. For a lengthier introduction to the History of Madness, see Gary Gutting’s chapter “Foucault and the History of Madness” in the Cambridge Companion to Foucault (Gutting 2005, pp. 49–73). A full English translation of Foucault’s book became available in 2006; until then, Richard Howard’s highly abbreviated translation, Madness and Civilization: A History of Insanity in the Age of Reason, delimited Anglo-American discussions of Foucault’s study.

  5. Even as Kierkegaard’s arguments were piercingly directed to his “present age” (as the title of one of his books attests), they purport to be more than historical reporting; they presume the reach of truth, forward and backwards. To wit: nineteenth-century Denmark may have suffered from spiritlessness as a sad consequence of the leveling of crowds, but faith in Christ will always be opposed to such lack of subjective inwardness because of the personal nature of faith and because of the link between faith and the absurd.

  6. Bicêtre was a prison that was transformed into a mental hospital in 1656.

  7. A further likeness between Foucault and Kierkegaard is their strong distaste for Descartes. On Kierkegaard and Descartes, see Rasmussen (2009). On Foucault and Derrida’s debate on how to interpret Descartes, see Davidson (1997).

  8. One literally ‘spectacular’ exception is the paid Sunday pastime of showing the mad, as if they were trained monkeys (Foucault 2009, pp. 143–44).

  9. This paradox of guilty innocence takes a slightly different form in the classical experience of madness, as innocence there is linked to animality rather than illness (Gutting 2005, p. 62).

  10. In Kierkegaard’s Concept of Anxiety, there are three approaches to what is called “the demonic.” As George Pattison recounts them, they are “the aesthetic-metaphysical, which regards it as a kind of fate suffered by the demonic person to whom we should therefore be essentially compassionate; the ethical, where being possessed is the moral fault of the one concerned, and therefore calls for punishment; and the medical-therapeutic, where it is to be treated as a physical illness. These are not necessarily exclusive, and Vigilius comments that this division shows that the demonic does indeed belong in all three spheres: the somatic, the psychic, and the pneumatic” (Pattison 2013, p. 70, emphasis added). These approaches to the demonic accord surprisingly well with the sense in Foucault’s History of Madness that the mad were objects of compassion under the Renaissance, received punishment under the classical age, and underwent medical treatment during the clinical period.

  11. By contrast, Kant offers a highly rational and clearly delineated classification of mental weakness in the cognitive faculty as well as of mental ailments (Kant 2006, §§45–53, pp. 96–115). In going to press, I discovered Hannah Lyn Venable’s tightly argued “At the Opening of Madness: An Exploration of the Nonrational with Merleau-Ponty, Foucault, and Kierkegaard,” in which Venable proposes three forms of the nonrational, namely, the prerational, irrational, and suprarational (Venable 2019, p. 476).

  12. In his reading of Climacus’s position in Philosophical Fragments, C. Stephen Evans distinguishes a formal, logical contradiction from the apparent contradiction of a paradox (Evans 1992, pp. 98, 104).

  13. Unless otherwise specified, all references to the Concluding Unscientific Postscript are to its first volume.

  14. As we will see, Richard McCombs maintains that irrationality is a pretense that Kierkegaard uses in order to communicate rationality (McCombs 1993, p. 19).

  15. Cf. Foucault (2009, p. 92) on profane speech. On the discontinuous quality of sudden, involuntary self-communication, see Pattison (2013, p. 70).

  16. In an especially Kierkegaardian moment, Foucault describes the madman’s instant of choice: “The liberty of the madman is only ever in that instant, that imperceptible distance that makes a man free to abandon his liberty and chain himself to his madness: it is there only in that virtual point of choice, where we elect to ‘put ourselves in the impossibility of using our freedom and correcting our mistakes’ [Boissier de Sauvages, Nosologie méthodique, VII, p. 4]” (Foucault 2009, p. 513). See also Bennington (2011) on Derrida’s quotation of Kierkegaard (“… L’Instant de la Décision est une Folie. …”) in a lecture on Foucault.

  17. Even in Fearless Speech, the theme of political veridiction is not linked with madness. There, the person who speaks truth to power does so under the banner of servitude rather than madness (Foucault 2001, p. 32).

  18. Subjectivity is opposed both to objectivity and to a cheap kind of sociality, which is marked by its own speech pattern, namely, chatter. See Fenves (1993).

  19. Here, too, one finds comforting moderation; for, de Silentio offers the qualification that in the religious the ethical is not surrendered outright but is dialectically suspended: “that which is suspended is not relinquished but is preserved in the higher, which is its telos” (Kierkegaard 1983, p. 54).

  20. In a passage on the relative worth of passion and understanding, Climacus muses: “I have considered it demeaning if I were to be more ashamed before human beings and their judgment than before the god and his judgment …. And who are those people, anyway, the ones I am supposed to fear—a few geniuses, perhaps, some literary critics …? … Or what are those people compared with the god; what is the refreshment of their busy clangor compared with the deliciousness of that solitary wellspring that is in every human being, that wellspring in which the god resides, that wellspring in the profound silence when all is quiet!” (Kierkegaard 1992, p. 183). The people who drink from the “busy clangor” of the literary critic of religion will thirst again; for eternal refreshment, one must plunge in the divine silence that—please note—“is in every human being.”

  21. Different statements in Fear and Trembling attest to the relationship between anxiety and paradox. For example: “Sweet sentimental longing leads us to the goal of our desire, to see Christ walking about in the promised land. We forget the anxiety, the distress, the paradox” (Kierkegaard 1983, p. 66; cf. Kierkegaard 1983, pp. 63–4).

  22. Kierkegaard writes similarly in his own name in Upbuilding Discourses in Various Spirits: “When a singular thinker, who through his singularity is more related to the eternal and less to the moment of temporality, addresses his discourse to people, he is rarely understood or listened to. If, however, a garrulous adherent comes to his aid so that the singular thinker can be—misunderstood—then it never fails, then there are many who promptly understand it” (Kierkegaard 1993, p. 90).

  23. Vanessa Rumble notes indirect communication’s link to freedom, describing Climacus’s discursive theory as “a demand for an unwavering consciousness of the freedom of both communicator and recipient” (Rumble 1995, p. 314). See, for example, Kierkegaard (1992, p. 74).

  24. On the relationship between inferiority, indirect communication, and being incognito, see Kierkegaard (1991, pp. 129–131). Socrates and Christ (like Abraham) would forfeit their unrecognizability as soon as they engaged in direct communication.

  25. Silence and solitude are necessary for cultivating subjectivity, but theirs is a free necessity. That is, insane asylums and other institutions work against authentic interiority by enforcing these conditions. As Zook explains, “[s]olitude is essential for the discovery of self-hood, but it only contributes to authenticity and subjectivity if the solitude is self-imposed and voluntary—choice is absolutely essential here. This is why Kierkegaard condemned the enforced silence of solitary confinement in prisons (Pap. 47 viii I A 40; P/J 258; SKS 7, 11; CUP 8) and why he argued against the obligatory, institutionalized silence of monastic retreats (SV3 17, 60; FSE 15)” (Zook 2008, pp. 402–3).

  26. The escapee becomes free by leaping through a window. Reading this detail with the knight of faith’s leap in mind allows for the interpretation that the madhouse represents the finite realm, out of which the knight of faith launches himself and back to which he gracefully returns (Kierkegaard 1983, p. 41).

  27. See chapter 4, “Subjectivity,” in Kelly (2009, pp. 78–105). In particular, I wish to point out the quotation from Foucault’s Remarks on Marx, which Kelly includes on page 80. There, Foucault speaks of the simultaneity of people’s experiences in knowing an objective set of things and people’s self-formation under determinate conditions as subjects.

  28. Among the extensive body of literature on the rhetorical choices of each thinker, see Aumann (2010), Freundlieb (1995), Megill (1990), Mooney (2013), Poole (1993), Pugh (1992), Söderquist (2013) and Taylor (1975). To the best of my knowledge, “Voices of Madness in Foucault and Kierkegaard” is the first work bringing Foucault and Kierkegaard’s literary styles directly into conversation with each other.

  29. Kierkegaard drew inspiration for his communication style from the masters of indirection, Socrates and Johann Georg Hamann (Kosch 2008, p. 72). I wonder if God communicates slyly, too. Is the incarnation, for example, indirect communication?

  30. Regarding Foucault’s indecipherability, Anthony Pugh asks the translator’s question of whether a line of nonsense in French should be rendered so as to make sense in English (Pugh 1992, p. 132).

  31. Cf. Pugh (1992, p. 134): “Speaking ‘for’ but not of course quoting the mad, Foucault can only express the pathos of their plight by means of rhetoric.”

  32. “Whereas politics offers the promise of an equality whereby we have all been leveled down, Christianity holds the promise of an equality whereby we have all been built up” (Aroosi 2016, p. 75). De Silentio seems to be in agreement with Haufniensis when he states, “[f]aith is a marvel, and yet no human being is excluded from it; for that which unites all human life is passion, and faith is a passion” (Kierkegaard 1983, p. 67). In a footnote to this passage, de Silentio quotes Lessing’s remark, denn die Leidenschaften machen alle Menschen wieder gleich, which translates “for the passions make all men equal again” (original emphasis).

  33. Cf. Kierkegaard (1980, p. 120).

  34. Within the limits of what remains of their self-representation, Roy Porter also features the vox insanorum in his social history of madness (2004, pp. 229–71).

References

  • Aroosi, J. (2016). The causes of bourgeois culture: Kierkegaard’s relation to Marx considered. Philosophy and Social Criticism,42(1), 71–92.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aumann, A. (2010). Kierkegaard on indirect communication, the crowd, and a monstrous illusion. In R. L. Perkins (Ed.), International Kierkegaard commentary: Point of view (Vol. 22, pp. 295–324). Macon, GA: Mercer UP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bennington, G. (2011). A moment of madness: Derrida’s Kierkegaard. Oxford Literary Review,33(1), 103–127.

    Google Scholar 

  • Caputo, J. D. (2004). On not knowing who we are: Madness, hermeneutics and the night of truth in Foucault. In J. Bernauer & J. Carrette (Eds.), Michel Foucault and theology: The politics of religious experience (pp. 117–139). Burlington, VT: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, A. I. (Ed.). (1997). Foucault and his interlocutors. Chicago: University of Chicago.

    Google Scholar 

  • Evans, C. S. (1992). Passionate reason: Making sense of Kierkegaard’s philosophical fragments. Bloomington, IN: Indiana UP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Felman, S. (1975). Madness and philosophy or literature’s reason. Yale French Studies,52, 206–228.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fenves, P. (1993). “Chatter”: Language and history in Kierkegaard. Stanford: Stanford UP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, M. (1972). Histoire de la folie à l’âge classique. Paris: Gallimard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, M. (2000). Power: Essential works of Foucault 1954–1984 (Vol. 3, J. D. Faubion, Ed., R. Hurley, Trans.). New York: New Press.

  • Foucault, M. (2001). Fearless speech (J. Pearson, Ed.). Los Angeles: Semiotext(e).

  • Foucault, M. (2009). History of madness (J. Murphy & J. Khalfa, Trans.). London: Routledge.

  • Foucault, M. (2015). Language, madness, and desire: On literature (P. Artières & J.-F. Bert, Eds.) Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

  • Freundlieb, D. (1995). Foucault and the study of literature. Poetics Today,16(2), 301–344.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gutting, G. (2005). Foucault and the history of madness. In G. Gutting (Ed.), Cambridge companion to Foucault (2nd ed., pp. 49–73). New York: Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hall, R. L. (1985). Language and freedom: Kierkegaard’s analysis of the demonic in the concept of anxiety. In R. L. Perkins (Ed.), International Kierkegaard commentary: The concept of anxiety (Vol. 8, pp. 153–166). Macon, GA: Mercer UP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huffer, L. (2013). The persistence of unreason: Michel Foucault’s mad melodrama. Criticism,55(4), 637–653.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (2006). Anthropology from a pragmatic point of view (R. B. Louden, Ed. & Trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge UP.

  • Kant, I. (2018). Religion within the boundaries of mere reason (A. Wood, Trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge UP.

  • Kelly, M. G. E. (2009). The political philosophy of Michel Foucault. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelly, M. G. E. (2014). Foucault and politics: A critical introduction. Edinburgh: Edinburgh UP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kierkegaard, S. (1962). The point of view for my work as an author (B. Nelson, Ed., W. Lowrie, Trans.). New York: Harper Torchbooks.

  • Kierkegaard, S. (1980). Concept of anxiety (R. Thomte, Trans.). Princeton: Princeton UP.

  • Kierkegaard, S. (1983). Fear and trembling (H. V. Hong & E. H. Hong, Eds. & Trans.). Princeton: Princeton UP.

  • Kierkegaard, S. (1985). Philosophical fragments (H. V. Hong & E. H. Hong, Eds. & Trans.). Princeton: Princeton UP.

  • Kierkegaard, S. (1987). Either/or (Vol. 1–2, H. V. Hong & E. H. Hong, Eds. & Trans.). Princeton: Princeton UP.

  • Kierkegaard, S. (1991). Practice in christianity (H. V. Hong & E. H. Hong, Eds. & Trans.). Princeton: Princeton UP.

  • Kierkegaard, S. (1992). Concluding unscientific postscript to philosophical fragments (Vol. 1–2, H. V. Hong & E. H. Hong, Eds. & Trans.). Princeton: Princeton UP.

  • Kierkegaard, S. (1993). Upbuilding discourses in various spirits (H. V. Hong & E. H. Hong, Eds. & Trans.). Princeton: Princeton UP.

  • Kosch, M. (2008). What Abraham couldn’t say. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes,82, 59–78.

    Google Scholar 

  • LaCapra, D. (2000). History and reading: Tocqueville, Foucault, French studies. Toronto: University of Toronto.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levine, M. P. (1982). Kierkegaard: What does the subjective individual risk? International Journal for Philosophy of Religion,13(1), 13–22.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lippitt, J. (2000). Humour and irony in Kierkegaard’s thought. New York: St. Martin’s Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Llewelyn, J. (2008). Margins of religion: Between Kierkegaard and Derrida. Bloomington, IN: Indiana UP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marino, G. D. (1987). Is madness truth, is fanaticism faith? International Journal for Philosophy of Religion,22(1), 41–53.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marino, G. D. (1998). Anxiety in the concept of anxiety. In A. Hannay & G. D. Marino (Eds.), Cambridge companion to Kierkegaard (pp. 308–328). Cambridge: Cambridge UP.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCombs, R. (1993). Paradoxical rationality of Søren Kierkegaard. Indianapolis: Indiana UP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Megill, A. (1990). Foucault, ambiguity, and the rhetoric of historiography. History of the Human Sciences,3(3), 343–361.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, E. L. (1997). At the centre of Kierkegaard: An objective absurdity. Religious Studies,33, 433–441.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, J. (2000). The passion of Michel Foucault. Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mooney, E. F. (2013). Pseudonyms and ‘style’. In J. Lippitt & G. Pattison (Eds.), Oxford Handbook of Kierkegaard (pp. 191–210). Oxford: Oxford UP.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Hara, D. T. (2017). Parables of the anonymous God in Nietzsche and Foucault. symplokē, 26(1–2), 427–434.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Leary, T., & Falzon, C. (Eds.). (2010). Foucault and philosophy. Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oskala, J. (2007). How to read Foucault. London: Granta Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pascal, B. (1995). Pensées (A. J. Krailsheimer, Trans.). New York: Penguin Books.

  • Pattison, G. (2013). Kierkegaard and the quest for unambiguous life: Between romanticism and modernism: Selected essays. Oxford: Oxford UP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Phillips, J. (2009). Madness of the philosophers, madness of the clinic. Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology,16(4), 313–317.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plato. (1997). Complete Works. J. M. Cooper (Ed.). Indianapolis: Hackett.

  • Poole, R. (1993). Kierkegaard: The indirect communication. Charlottesville: University Press of Virginia.

    Google Scholar 

  • Porter, R. (2004). Madmen: A social history of madhouses, mad-doctors and lunatics. Gloucestershire: Tempus.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pugh, A. (1992). Foucault, rhetoric and translation: Figures of madness. In A. Still & I. Velody (Eds.), Rewriting the history of madness: Studies in Foucault’s Histoire de la folie (pp. 126–141). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rasmussen, A. M. (2009). René Descartes: Kierkegaard’s understanding of doubt and certainty. In J. Stewart (Ed.), Kierkegaard and the Renaissance and modern traditions: Philosophy (pp. 11–22). Burlington, VT: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rumble, V. (1995). To be as no-one: Kierkegaard and Climacus on the art of indirect communication. International Journal of Philosophical Studies,3(2), 307–321.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scull, A. (1990). Michel Foucault’s history of madness. History of the Human Sciences,3(1), 57–67.

    Google Scholar 

  • Söderquist, K. B. (2013). Irony. In J. Lippitt & G. Pattison (Eds.), Oxford handbook of Kierkegaard (pp. 344–364). Oxford: Oxford UP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, M. C. (1975). Kierkegaard’s pseudonymous authorship: A study of time and the self. Princeton: Princeton UP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Venable, H. L. (2019). At the opening of madness: An exploration of the nonrational with Merleau-Ponty, Foucault, and Kierkegaard. The Journal of Speculative Philosophy, 33(3), 475–488.

    Google Scholar 

  • Warren, M. L. (2009). The Quakers as parrhesiasts: Frank speech and plain speaking as the fruits of silence. Quaker History,98(2), 1–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zook, D. C. (2008). The irony of it all: Søren Kierkegaard and the anxious pleasures of civil society. British Journal for the History of Philosophy,16(2), 393–419.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I wish to thank Shterna Friedman, Johanna Magin, and the anonymous reviewer for engaging this piece critically and with good will.

Funding

Funding was provided by George Fox University (Grant No. GFU2019G04).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Heather C. Ohaneson.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Ohaneson, H.C. Voices of madness in Foucault and Kierkegaard. Int J Philos Relig 87, 27–54 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11153-019-09739-6

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11153-019-09739-6

Keywords

Navigation