Skip to main content
Log in

Self-ascription of intention: responsibility, obligation and self-control

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In the late preschool years children acquire a “theory of mind”, the ability to ascribe intentional states, including beliefs, desires and intentions, to themselves and others. In this paper I trace how children’s ability to ascribe intentions is derived from parental attempts to hold them responsible for their talk and action, that is, the attempt to have their behavior meet a normative standard or rule. Self-control is children’s developing ability to take on or accept responsibility, that is, the ability to ascribe intentions to themselves. This is achieved, I argue, when they possess the ability to hold an utterance or rule in mind in the form of a quoted expression, and second, when they grasp the causal relation between the rule and their action. The account of how children learn to ascribe intention to themselves and others will then be used to explore the larger question of the relations amongst language, intentional states and the ascription and avowal of those states.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Astington J.W. (1988). Children’s understanding of the speech act of promising. Journal of Child Language 15, 157–163

    Google Scholar 

  • Astington J.W. (1993). The child’s discovery of the mind. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Astington, J. W. (2001). The paradox of intention: Assessing children’s metarepresentational understanding. In B. F. Malle, L. J. Moses, & D. A. Baldwin (Eds.), Intentions and intentionality: Foundations of social cognition. Cambridge, MA: Bradford Books/MIT.

  • Astington J.W., Baird J.A. (eds). (2005a): Why language matters to the theory of mind. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Astington J.W., Baird J.A. (2005b). Representational development and false-belief understanding. In: Astington J.W., Baird J.A. (eds). Why language matters to the theory of mind. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp. 163–185

    Google Scholar 

  • Astington J.W., Baird J.A. (2005c). Introduction: Why language matters. In: Astington J.W., Baird J.A., (eds). Why language matters to the theory of mind. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp. 3–25

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandom R. (2000). Articulating reasons: An introduction to inferentialism. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Bruner J.S. (1996). The culture of education. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Case R. (1985). Intellectual development: Birth to adulthood. Academic Press, Orlando, FA

    Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers P. (1996). Language, thought and consciousness. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson D. (1984). Inquiries into truth and interpretation. Oxford University Press, Oxford, UK

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett D. (1978). Brainstorms. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • De Villiers P. (2005a). The role of language in theory of mind development: What deaf children tell us. In: Astington J.W., Baird J.A. (eds). Why language matters for theory of mind. Oxford University Press, Oxford, UK, pp. 266–297

    Google Scholar 

  • De Villiers J. (2005b). Can language acquisition give children a point of view. In: Astington J.W., Baird J.A., (eds). Why language matters for theory of mind. Oxford University Press, Oxford, UK, pp. 186–219

    Google Scholar 

  • Dummett M. (1973). Frege, philosophy of language. Duckworth, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Ely R., McCabe A. (1993). Remembered voices. Journal of Child Language 20, 671–699

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor J.A. (1975). The language of thought. Crowell, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor J.A. (1992). A theory of the child’s theory of mind. Cognition 44, 283–296

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldin-Meadow S. (2005). Gesture in social interactions: A mechanism for cognitive change. In: Homer B., Tamis-LeMonda C., (eds). The development of social cognition and communication. Erlbaum, Mahwah, NJ, pp. 259–283

    Google Scholar 

  • Harré, R. (2001). Norms in life: Problems in the representation of rules. In D. Bakhurst & S. Shanker (Eds.), Jerome Bruner: Language, culture, self. London: Sage.

  • Hickman M. (1993). The boundaries of reported speech in narrative discourse: Some developmental aspects. In: Lucy J. (eds). Reflexive language: Reported speech and metapragmatics. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge UK, pp. 63–90

    Google Scholar 

  • Homer B., Olson D.R. (1999). Literacy and children’s conception of words. Written Language and Literacy 2, 113–137

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackendoff R. (2002). Foundations of language. Oxford University Press, Oxford, UK

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn D., Pearsall S. (2000). Developmental origins of scientific thinking. Journal of Cognitive Development 1, 113–127

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lancy D. (1996). Playing on the mother ground. Guildford Press, NY

    Google Scholar 

  • Latour B., Woolgar W. (1986). Laboratory life: The construction of scientific facts. Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ

    Google Scholar 

  • Leech G.N. (1983). Principles of pragmatics. Longmans, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Leslie A.M. (1987). Pretense and representation: The origins of ‘Theory of Mind’. Psychological Review 94, 412–426

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Olson D.R. (1989). Making up your mind. Canadian Psychology 30, 617–627

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Olson D.R. (1994). The world on paper: The conceptual and cognitive implications of writing and reading. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK

    Google Scholar 

  • Olson D.R. (2005). The computational mind and the digitized society: A question of rules. Explorations in Media Ecology 4, 3–10

    Google Scholar 

  • Olson D.R., Astington J.W. (1990). Talking about text: How literacy contributes to thought. Journal of Pragmatics 14, 705–721

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Olson D.R. & Kamawar D., (2002). Writing as a form of quotation. In: Brockmeier J., Wang M., Olson D.R. (eds). Literacy, narrative and culture. Curzon, Richmond Surrey, UK, pp. 187–198

    Google Scholar 

  • Perner J. (1991). Understanding the representational mind. Bradford Books/MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Perner J., Stummer S., Sprung M., Doherty M. (2002). Theory of mind finds its Piagetian perspective: Why alternative naming comes with understanding belief. Cognitive Development 17, 1451–1472

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Piaget J. (1932). The moral judgment of the child. Kegan Paul, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Piaget J. (1952). The origins of intelligence in children. Basic Books, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine W. (1960). Word and object. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosaldo M.Z. (1982). The things we do with words: Ilongot speech acts and speech act theory in philosophy. Language in Society 2, 203–237

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rozeboom W.W. (1972). Problems in the psycho-philosophy of knowledge. In: Royce J.R., Rozeboom W.W. (eds). The psychology of knowing. Gordon & Breach, NY, pp. 25–55

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell J. (1996). Agency: Its role in mental development. Erlbaum (UK) Taylor & Francis, Hove, UK

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle J. (1983). Intentionality. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK

    Google Scholar 

  • Shultz T.R., Wells D. (1985). Judging the intentionality of action-outcomes. Developmental Psychology 21, 83–89

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Skinner B.F. (1953). Science and human behavior. Macmillan, NewYork

    Google Scholar 

  • Snell B. (1960). The discovery of the mind. Harper & Row, NY

    Google Scholar 

  • Tishman S., Perkins D. (1997). The language of thinking. Phi Delta Kappan 78, 368–374

    Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello M. (1999). The cultural origins of human cognition. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Vendler, Z. (1970). Say what you think. In J. L. Cowan (Ed.), Studies in thought and language. University of Arizona Press, Tucson, AZ:

  • Vinden P.G. (1999). Children’s understanding of mind and emotion: A multi-culture study. Cognition and Emotion 13, 19–48

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Von Wright G.H. (1972). Explanation and understanding. Routledge & Kegan Paul, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein L. (1958). Philosophical investigations (G E M Anscombe, Trans). Blackwell, Oxford, UK

    Google Scholar 

  • Zelazo P.D. (1999). Language, levels of consciousness, and the development of intentional action. In: Zelazo P.D., Astington J.W., Olson D.R. (eds). Developing theories of intention: Social understanding and self-control. Erlbaum, Mahwah, NJ, pp. 95–117

    Google Scholar 

  • Zelazo P.D., Jacques S. (1996). Children’s rule use: Representation, reflection and cognitive control. Annals of Child Development 12, 119–176

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to David R. Olson.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Olson, D.R. Self-ascription of intention: responsibility, obligation and self-control. Synthese 159, 297–314 (2007). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-007-9209-2

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-007-9209-2

Keywords

Navigation