Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-cfpbc Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-24T07:06:44.803Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Universality and its Limits: When Research Ethics Can Reflect Local Circumstances

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2021

Extract

Studies in several developing countries for treatmen to prevent HIV-transmission from mother to child generated considerable controversy in 1997. Critics of the studies argued that basic principles of research ethics were violated. According to the critics, researchers subjected women in developing countries to studies that would have been unethical in the United States (and other developed countries) and that the researchers were therefore engaged in unethical exploitation ofcitizens of the developing countries in which the studies were conducted.

While the critics agreed that unethical exploitation had occurred, they differed on the exact nature of the exploitation. Some observers condemned the researchers for employing a double standard — because the researchers were applying a standard of care that would have been unacceptable in their own country. In the view of these critics, researchers should have been comparing the experimental treatment to established therapy rather than to placebo, as would have been required in the United States or other developed countries.

Type
Article
Copyright
Copyright © American Society of Law, Medicine and Ethics 2002

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Lurie, P. Wolfe, S.M., “Unethical Trials of Interventions to Reduce Perinatal Transmission of the Human Immunodeficiency Virus in Developing Countries,” N. Engl. J. Med., 337 (1997): 853–56, at 854–55.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crouch, R.A. Arras, J.D., “AZT Trials and Tribulations,” Hastings Center Report, 28, no. 6 (1998): 2634, at 29;.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Glantz, L.H. et al. , “Research in Developing Countries: Taking Benefit Seriously,” Hastings Center Report, 28, no. 6 (1998): 3842, at 40–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Connor, E.M. et al. , “Reduction of Maternal-Infant Transmission of Human Immunodeficiency Virus Type I with Zidovudine Treatment,” N. Engl. J. Med., 331 (1994): 1173–80.Google Scholar
AZT treatment began when the women entered the study, which occurred between weeks fourteen and thirty-four of their pregnancies. Id. at 1174.Google Scholar
Levine, C., “Placebos and HIV: Lessons Learned,” Hastings Center Report, 28, no. 6 (1998): 4348, at 44. To be sure, there is some artificiality to the stated cost of drug therapy. Companies may be able to price far above actual costs and exact monopoly profits for drugs under patent protection. Furthermore, public pressure has been successful in lowering the market price of important drugs. Nevertheless, it is clear that citizens of developing countries cannot afford drug treatments to the same extent as citizens of developed countries.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lurie, Wolfe, , supra note 1, at 853–54.Google Scholar
Id. at 854–55.Google Scholar
Rothman, K.J. Michels, K.B., “Declaration of Helsinki Should Be Strengthened: FOR,” British Medical Journal, 321 (2000): 442–45, at 443–44.Google Scholar
Varmus, H. Satcher, D., “Ethical Complexities of Conducting Research in Developing Countries,” N. Engl. J. Med., 337 (1997): 1003–05, at 1004–05; Crouch, Arras, , supra note 2, at 27.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Glantz, et al. , supra note 2, at 40-41.Google Scholar
This example is based loosely on the Kenya Program of the Indiana University School of Medicine.Google Scholar
Some people might reject the view that a U.S. citizen's obligations to citizens and residents of the U.S. are greater than the citizen's obligations to people living in other countries (who are not citizens of the U.S.). However, as a matter of ethics and law, national borders matter. When Congress funds health care coverage for older persons, it acts ethically when it limits coverage to people living in the United States. Similarly, the constitutional rights of U.S. citizens and residents under U.S. law exceed those of noncitizens living in other countries. This distinction between local residents and people living in other countries reflects a number of considerations. First, ties of kinship matter. We recognize the interest of people in devoting more of their money and time to family members over strangers, to local non-profit organizations over non-profits in other cities or states, to co-religionists over members of other religions, and to countrymen and women over people who live elsewhere. In addition, when people share citizenship or residency with each other, they share in a collection of rights and responsibilities. Nonresidents do not bear most of the responsibilities of community membership, and they therefore do not bear most of the rights of community membership.Google Scholar
Some people might find the drug company example unethical on grounds of exploitation, but I do not think we can condemn businesses simply because they bring a resource from a less developed country to a more developed country. It is not in the interest of developing countries if they are prevented from sending their fruits and vegetables, oil and gas, or precious minerals to other countries in exchange for goods that cannot be produced in their countries. The exploitation concern is discussed at length later in this article.Google Scholar
Furrow, B.R. et al. , Health Law, 2d ed. (St. Paul: West Group, 2000): at 265.Google Scholar
Baum, M., “Declaration of Helsinki Should Be Strengthened: AGAINST,” British Medical Journal, 321 (2000): 444–45, at 445.Google Scholar
Angell, M., “The Ethics of Clinical Research in the Third World,” N. Engl. J. Med., 337 (1997): 847–49, at 847.Google Scholar
Some critics have questioned whether in fact the women gave true informed consent, and other critics have observed that many of the women suffered stigmatization when their HIV status became known. These objections are important, but they would apply to any research done in the same communities, regardless of whether a placebo control was used or whether the experimental therapy studied was destined for use in developing or developed countries.Google Scholar
Lurie, Wolfe, , supra note 1, at 855.Google Scholar
Id. at 855.Google Scholar
Medical malpractice standards take into account local resources, but a physician practicing in an inner city clinic could not provide a lower level of care on account of the clinic's resources. Rather, if the patient needed care that could not be adequately provided in the clinic, the physician would transfer the patient to an appropriate facility.Google Scholar
In fact, the less aggressive, less expensive course of AZT treatment substantially reduces the risk of HIV-transmission from mother to infant, though not as effectively as the more aggressive, more expensive course of AZT. Grady, C., “Science in the Service of Healing,” Hastings Center Report, 28, no. 6 (1998): 3438, at 35–36.Google Scholar
Shapiro, H.T. Meslin, E.M., “Ethical Issues in the Design and Conduct of Clinical Trials in Developing Countries,” N. Engl. J. Med., 345 (2001): 139–42, at 140. See also National Bioethics Advisory Commission, Ethical and Policy Issues in International Research: Clinical Trials in Developing Countries, ISBN 931022-13-5 (April 2001), available at <http://www.georgetown.edu/research/nrcbl/nbac/pubs.html> (“[r]esearchers and sponsors should design clinical trials that provide members of any control group with an established effective treatment, whether or not such treatment is available in the host country.”).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
World Medical Association, “Declaration of Helsinki: Ethical Principles for Medical Research Involving Human Subjects,” JAMA, 284 (2000): 3043–45, ¶ 29, at 3045 In an October 2001 clarification, the World Medical Association indicated that placebo controls can be used even when proven therapy exists if (1) the placebo control is necessary to establish the safety or efficacy of an experimental therapy, or (2) the experimental therapy is designed for treatment of a “minor condition” and receiving the placebo will not increase the risk of “serious or irreversible harm.”CrossRefGoogle Scholar
See World Medical Association, Note of Clarification on Paragraph 29 of the WMA Declaration of Helsinki (October 7, 2001), at <http://www.wma.net/e/policy/17-c_e.html#clarification> (last visited October 4, 2002).+(last+visited+October+4,+2002).>Google Scholar
Levine, R.J., “Some Recent Developments in the International Guidelines on the Ethics of Research Involving Human Subjects,” Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, 918 (2000): 170–78, at 174–76.Google Scholar
Varmus, Satcher, , supra note 9, at 1004-05;.Google Scholar
Crouch, Arras, , supra note 2, at 27.Google Scholar
Placebo controls — even when there is an established therapy — also have value for other kinds of studies. When testing an experimental therapy, one can determine whether it is effective with a smaller number of subjects if the experimental therapy is compared to a placebo rather than to established therapy. Emanuel, E.J. Miller, F.G., “The Ethics of Placebo-Controlled Trials — A Middle Ground,” N. Engl. J. Med, 345 (2001): 915–19, at 916. For additional discussion of the justifications of placebo-controlled trials see Orentlicher, D., “Placebo-Controlled Trials of New Drugs: Ethical Considerations,” Diabetes Care, 24 (2001): 771–72.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
See Council for International Organizations of Medical Sciences, International Ethical Guidelines for Biomedical Research Involving Human Subjects, Guideline 10, at <http://cioms.ch/frame_guidelines_sept_2002.htm> (revised August 2002).+(revised+August+2002).>Google Scholar
Feinberg, J., The Moral Limits of the Criminal Law: Harmless Wrongdoing (New York: Oxford University Press, 1988): 176210.Google Scholar
Id. at 204–10.Google Scholar
Glantz, et al. , supra note 2, at 40-41.Google Scholar
Council for International Organizations of Medical Sciences, supra note 27.Google Scholar
Crouch and Arras, supra note 2, at 30-31.Google Scholar