Skip to main content
Log in

Hypothesis formation and testing in the acquisition of representationally simple concepts

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Observations from philosophy and psychology heavily favor the Empiricist tenet that many lexical concepts are learned. However, many observations also heavily favor the Nativist tenet that such concepts are representationally atomic. Fodor (The language of thought, 1975, In J. Fodor (Ed.) Representations: Philosophical essays on the foundations of cognitive science, 1981, LOT2: The language of thought revisited, 2008) has famously argued that representationally atomic concepts cannot be learned, at least not learned by hypothesis formation and testing. Concept theorists who want to preserve observations about concept learning have developed acquisition models on which the acquired concepts are either non-atomic or are acquired by a process that doesn’t involve hypothesis formation and testing. I offer a model, Baptizing Meanings for Concepts (BMC), in which representationally atomic concepts are learned by hypothesis formation and testing. The concepts are learned by the agent’s hypothesizing the existence of a latent/hidden/imperceptible property in objects to explain the objects’ perceptible similarities. Once a hidden property is hypothesized, a new atomic mental name is assigned to it, and this atomic name becomes the concept. Any connections between the name and the representations involved in linking the name to its referent are stored as contingent. Further experience may give the agent reason to revise its hypotheses about latent properties as explanations for its observations. I discuss a software robot implementation of the BMC process that uses a Bayesian learning network. The implementation provides an existence proof of the possibility of learning representationally atomic concepts by hypothesis formation and testing.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4
Fig. 5
Fig. 6

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. I first explored this account in a poster called “The Mental Coining of Terms” at the 2007 meeting of the Society for Philosophy and Psychology.

  2. This is how ‘concept’ is used among cognitive scientists, in contrast with the philosopher’s use of ‘concept’ for the meanings of linguistic and/or mental terms. I distinguish between a token concept as a stored mental entity in an individual cognizer and the tokenizing of a concept that happens when a cognizer brings the stored entity into occurrent thought-processing.

  3. What is on offer is not a metaphysical account of what it is to have a concept. Whatever it is to have a concept, the BMC process offers a pathway to that state of affairs.

  4. I hesitate to call the hidden/latent/unobservable property an essence, because different properties may be posited to explain different collections of known properties across different collections of objects (apple, fruit, McIntosh, etc.).

  5. Kripke (1972), Putnam (1975), Burge (1979), Soames (2002).

  6. Some psychologists do seem to be trying to do something like this when they ask subjects to figure out the meaning of a linguistic term, “blik”. That, however, is not what it is to learn a concept as I have characterized it, even if it involves hypothesis formation and testing. There is a genuine question about whether lexical concepts, like APPLE, are learned by an inferential process that is akin to the acquisition of phrasal concepts, like TALKING APPLE.

  7. It’s not quite a mental version of the linguistic process because the linguistic process relies on concept possession, for dealing with the qua-problem in particular, as discussed later in this paper.

  8. No claims are being made presently about the actual perceptual space of human beings. The example serves merely to illustrate the kind of process that allows for the acquisition of atomic concepts.

  9. Frege’s Puzzle is introduced in his (1892).

  10. Fodor discusses the explicit/implicit issue in his (1983). Robert Matthews challenges the distinction in his (2007).

  11. A full defense of such concepts as genuinely atomic appears in my doctoral dissertation (Oved 2009).

  12. A real-world robot was also built, as reported in Rebguns et al. (2011).

  13. Notice that Putnam is careful to include ‘liquid’ in the presupposition, to ensure that the term ‘water’ gets hooked onto the property of being water rather than any of the other properties in the sample.

References

  • Burge, T. (1979). Individualism and the mental. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 4, 73–121.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carey, S. (1985). Conceptual change in childhood. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carey, S. (2009). The origin of concepts. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (1975). The language of thought. New York: Thomas Y. Crowell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (1981). The present status of the innateness controversy. In J. Fodor (Ed.), Representations: Philosophical essays on the foundations of cognitive science (pp. 257–316). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (1983). The modularity of mind. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (1985). Fodor’s guide to mental representation. Mind, 94, 76–100.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (1998). Concepts: Where cognitive science went wrong. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (2008). LOT2: The language of thought revisited. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1892) Über Sinn und Bedeutung. In Zeitschrift für Philosophie und philosophische Kritik, 100, 25–50. Translated as ‘On Sense and Reference’ by M. Black in Translations from the Philosophical Writings of Gottlob Frege (3rd ed.), P. Geach and M. Black (eds. and trans.), Oxford: Blackwell, 1980.

  • Gopnik, A., Glymour, C., Sobel, D. M., Schulz, L. E., Kushnir, T., & Danks, D. (2004). A theory of causal learning in children: Causal maps and Bayes nets. Psychological Review, 111(1), 3–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gopnik, A., & Schulz, L. (2007). Causal learning: Psychology, philosophy, and computation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gopnik, A., & Wellman, H. (2012). Reconstructing constructivism: Causal models, Bayesian learning mechanisms, and the theory theory. Psychological Bulletin, 138(6), 1085–1108.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kemp, C., Perfors, A., & Tennenbaum, J. (2007). Learning overhypotheses with hierarchical Bayesian models. Developmental Science, 10, 307–321.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. A. (1972). Naming and necessity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Locke, J. (1690). An essay concerning human understanding. London: Thomas Basset.

    Google Scholar 

  • Margolis, E. (1998). How to acquire a concept. Mind and Language, 13(3), 347–369.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Matthews, R. (2007). The measure of mind: Propositional attitudes and their attribution. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell, T. (1997). Machine learning. New York: McGraw Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oved, I. (2009). Baptizing meanings for concepts. Doctoral Dissertation. Rutgers University.

  • Oved, I., & Fasel, I. (2010). Philosophically inspired concept acquisition for artificial general intelligence. In Pthroceedings of the 4th Conference of Artificial General Intelligence.

  • Pearl, J. (2000). Causality: Models, reasoning, and inference (1st ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Pearl, J. (2009). Causality: Models, reasoning, and inference (2nd ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1975). The meaning of meaning. In H. Putnam (Ed.), Philosophical papers: Mind, language and reality (Vol. 2, pp. 215–271). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Rebguns, A., Ford, D., & Fasel, I. (2011). InfoMax control for acoustic exploration of objects by a mobile robot. AAAI Workshop on Lifelong Learning, 2011.

  • Rupert, R. (2001). Coining terms in the language of thought: Innateness, emergence, and the lot of Cummins’s argument against the causal theory of mental content. Journal of Philosophy, 98, 499–530.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Soames, S. (2002). Beyond rigidity: The unfinished semantic agenda of naming and necessity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Vallabha, G. K., McClelland, J. L., Pons, F., Werker, J. F., & Amano, S. (2007). Unsupervised learning of vowel categories from infant-directed speech. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 104, 33.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilt, A., Fasel, I., Mafi, N., Morrison, C., & Oved, I. (submitted). Unsupervised concept discovery through intrinsically motivated exploration.

  • Xu, F., & Tenenbaum, J. (2007). Sensitivity to sampling in Bayesian word learning. Developmental Science, 10, 288–297.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Iris Oved.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Oved, I. Hypothesis formation and testing in the acquisition of representationally simple concepts. Philos Stud 172, 227–247 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-014-0291-2

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-014-0291-2

Keywords

Navigation