Skip to main content
Log in

Creation and End-Directedness

  • Published:
Sophia Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Does the act of creation show itself anywhere within the creation? A common contemporary ontology tends to see two possibilities for those who want to defend a notion of creation. The first is to argue that an original set of materials was brought into existence out of nothing by divine action a long time ago. The second, in the tradition of Paley, posits a specific divine action that oversees the development of some of the materials into entities with an end-directedness. Much contemporary energy focuses on the second possibility. The argument of the paper is that the ontology behind both of these possibilities, which limits itself to the notions of a creation of materials and the building of some of the materials into end-directed entities, conceals rather than reveals the idea of creation. The paper tries to show how an Aristotelian sense of nature, with its recognition of internal teleology and original spontaneity, offers a better starting point for coming up against the mystery of divine creative activity.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. A poultry company situated in northern Victoria

  2. ‘(I)f a man were to make a machine for some special purpose, but were to use old wheels, springs and pulleys, only slightly altered, the whole machine, with all its parts, might be said to be specially contrived for its present purpose. Thus throughout nature almost every part of each living being has probably served in a slightly modified condition, for diverse purposes, and has acted in the living machinery of many ancient and distinct forms’ (Darwin 1862: 348).

  3. The point is nicely summed-up in a title of William A. Dembski: No Free Lunch: Why Specified Complexity Cannot Be Purchased Without Intelligence (Dembski 2002).

  4. For example, Nancey Murphy believes that as neuroscience progressively reduces faculties of the mind to the functioning of certain regions or systems of the brain ‘it becomes more and more appealing to say that it is in fact the brain that performs these functions’ (Murphy 1998: 13).

  5. The philosopher Michael Ruse has a succinct expression of this view: ‘it has proven impossible to distinguish between a biological phenomenon like sweating and a non-biological phenomenon like a swinging pendulum, because, questions of function apart, there is no essential difference’ (Ruse 1973: 192).

References

  • Aquinas, St. Thomas. (1967). Creation, variety and evil. Trans. Thomas Gilby O.P. Summa Theologiae. UK: Blackfriars, Eyre and Spottiswoode, Vol. 8.

  • Aquinas, St. Thomas. (1975). Divine government. Trans. T.C. O’Brien. Summa Theologiae. UK: Blackfriars, Eyre and Spottiswoode, Vol. 14.

  • Aquinas, St. Thomas. (1995). Commentary on Aristotle’s metaphysics. Notre Dame, Indiana: Dumb Ox Books.

  • Aristotle. (1984). Metaphysics. Trans. W.D. Ross. In Jonathan Barnes (Ed.), The complete works of Aristotle (pp.1552-1728). New Jersey: Princeton University Press. Vol. 2.

  • Aristotle. (1984). On generation and corruption. Trans. H.H. Joachim. In Jonathan Barnes (Ed.), The complete works of Aristotle (pp.512-554). New Jersey: Princeton University Press. Vol. 1.

  • Aristotle. (1984). On the soul. Trans. J.A. Smith. In Jonathan Barnes (Ed.), The complete works of Aristotle (pp.641-692). New Jersey: Princeton University Press. Vol. 1.

  • Aristotle. (1984). The Physics. Trans. R.P. Hardie and R.K. Gaye. In Jonathan Barnes (Ed.), The Complete Works of Aristotle (pp.315-446). New Jersey: Princeton University Press. Vol. 1.

  • Condic, M. L. (2008). When does life begin? New York: The Westchester Institute for Ethics & The Human Person.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwin, C. (1862). On the various contrivances by which British and Foreign orchids are fertilized by insects, and on the good effects of intercrossing. London: John Murray.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dembski, W. A. (2002). No free lunch: Why specified complexity cannot be purchased without intelligence. Maryland: Rowan and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. (1976). In A. Wayne Colver & P. John Vladimir (Eds.), Dialogues concerning natural religion. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kenny, A. (1992). The metaphysics of mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Murphy, N. (1998). Human nature: historical, scientific, and religious issues. In W. S. Brown, N. Murphy, & H. N. Malony (Eds.), Whatever happened to the soul? (pp.1-29). Minneapolis: Fortress Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Paley, W. (1837). Natural theology. Edinburgh: William and Robert Chambers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruse, M. (1973). The philosophy of biology. London: Hutchinson.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to John F. Owens.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Owens, J.F. Creation and End-Directedness. SOPHIA 49, 489–498 (2010). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11841-010-0218-0

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11841-010-0218-0

Keywords

Navigation