What is "Tantalizing" about the "Gap"

in Kant’s Philosophical System?

 

Prof. Stephen Palmquist, D.Phil. (Oxon)

Department of Religion and Philosophy

Hong Kong Baptist University

(stevepq@hkbu.edu.hk)

 

I am as it were mentally paralyzed even though physically I am reasonably well. I see before me the unpaid bill of my uncompleted philosophy, even while I am aware that philosophy, both as regards its means and its ends, is capable of completion. It is a pain like that of Tantalus though not a hopeless pain. The project on which I am now working concerns the "Transition from the metaphysical foundations of natural science to physics." It must be completed, or else a gap will remain in the critical philosophy. Reason will not give up her demands for this ... [KPC 251][1]

 

I. The "Gap" and the "Transition": Förster's New Interpretation

 

        In this famous passage from a 1798 letter to Christian Garve, Kant confesses that he sees a tantalizing "gap" in his philosophical System, a gap connected in some way with the "Transition" project he was then working on, as contained in what we now call Kant's Opus Postumum (OP). Interpreters have typically assumed that the "gap" and the "Transition" refer ßto exactly the same thing, namely, to the book Kant hoped OP would become. As a result, there has been a long-standing, twofold conundrum concerning Kant's intentions in OP. First, Kant clearly states in his Critique of Judgment (CJ) that with this book (published in 1790) he brings his "entire critical undertaking to a close" [CJ 170], so how can a new gap suddenly appear eight years later? And second, Kant's Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science (MFNS) had already accomplished, in 1786, something like a transition between the Critical System and physics, so why does there need to be another transition between this first transition and physics? These twin problems have led some scholars to suppose that, when Kant mentions mental paralysis in his letter to Garve, he is actually referring to the onset of senility, and that this affliction eventually caused the sage of Königsberg to waste the last years of his life writing nonsense.

 

        Eckart Förster has recently proposed an interesting new alternative explanation which, he argues, could provide some much-needed clues for drawing together the diverse pieces of this puzzle.[2]?/span>He argues that Kant must not have intended the words "gap" and "Transition" to refer to the same thing, because the idea for writing a Transition can be traced "back at least to the year 1790" [536], yet no mention of a gap is ever made until September of 1798 [537]. He thinks this indicates that something must have "happened in 1798 which prompted Kant to reflect anew on his philosophy, and which brought to his attention a gap in the critical system that had previously escaped him" [537]. Förster conjectures on the basis of an ingenious compilation of evidence that the event in question, which sparked Kant's recognition of the gap, was the publication of a Prize Essay question by the Berlin Academy of Sciences, criticizing Kant's view of mathematics and favoring "the general empirical origin of all our cognitions" [quoted in GAP 554]. This event, suggests Förster, may have "led Kant to reflect anew on the role of mathematics in philosophy and hence, ultimately, to revise his position substantially" [555]. Although he does not claim to have presented a thorough analysis, Förster points out that the theory of the role of mathematics in physics which Kant develops in OP appears to be contrary to the official "Critical" position [GAP 549-552]. This difference, Förster claims, suggests that the word "gap" refers to Kant's sudden, painful realization that "the question of the objective reality of [the first Critique's] concepts and principles still awaited a satisfactory demonstration" [GAP 551]—a question that would therefore need to be answered in OP as part of the Transition.

 

        Förster defends his position by noting that OP contains a "polemic against mathematical foundations" [GAP 550] that seems to contradict directly the view presented in MFNS, where mathematics is regarded as the necessary link between metaphysics and physics: "A pure philosophy of nature in general", Kant explains, "may indeed be possible without mathematics; but a pure doctrine of nature concerning determinate natural things ... is possible only by means of mathematics" [MFNS 470]. If in OP "mathematics is expelled from the philosophia naturalis", then, Förster concludes, "the very possibility of a ‘pure doctrine of nature ...' is now in question" [GAP 550]. Thus the new gap that Kant supposedly recognized suddenly in September of 1798 was that the function of MFNS (see below) must now be replaced by a non-mathematical defense of the objective reality (i.e., applicability to physics) of the categories and principles defended in CPR.

 

        Förster's new alternative, then, is that "Transition" refers to the book that was to be composed out of the notes contained in OP, whereas "gap" refers to the recognition while writing this book that his former "Critical" view of mathematics (as developed in MFNS) was mistaken and therefore needed to be replaced. Unfortunately, Förster has overlooked several problems that render his novel explanation untenable. After uncovering these problems, I shall demonstrate how they can be resolved by means of an alternative interpretation of the terms "gap" and "Transition".

 

        The first problem raised by Förster's conjecture is that it seems rather far-fetched to suppose that the person who is arguably the most influential philosopher in modern times, and who showed such extreme (often annoying) confidence in the validity of his work, would suddenly revise one of the most basic tenets of his (by then) well-established System, just because someone saw fit to question it. This would not be the recognition of a gap, but a revolutionary rejection of an important part of the Critical enterprise, in favor of something closer to traditional empiricism. Moreover, such an interpretation fails to explain why Kant would say repeatedly in OP that this book adopts the "highest standpoint of transcendental philosophy" [e.g., OP 23,32]. If OP is intended to revise such basic Critical doctrines as the role of mathematics in physics, then it would hardly seem appropriate for Kant to call it the highest standpoint of his System, but, at best, a revision of the standpoint formerly adopted erroneously! Yet, as I shall argue shortly, no such problematic revision need be supposed, once the thoroughly perspectival structure of Kant's philosophical System is taken into account. The views expressed in OP are in no sense intended to replace the views expressed in any of the three Critiques, but instead are intended to answer some of the same questions from a different standpoint. Solving this first problem, then, will require an explanation of how the apparently contradictory theories Kant proposes in MFNS and OP can be rendered compatible.

 

        The second problem arises when Förster [in GAP 538] denies the traditional view of MFNS, whereby it is regarded as a partial fulfillment of Kant's plan to write a Metaphysics of Nature.[3]?/span>Förster rightly recognizes that MFNS is "Kant's philosophy of physics, or, rather, of physics' rational part" [GAP 544]; however, he believes its function in Kant's System should be understood in connection not with the proposed Metaphysics of Nature, but with CPR, as a kind of extended footnote to the Schematism: "Since the Schematism chapter dealt exclusively with time-determinations and inner sense, it did not specify the ‘sufficient' conditions of the application of the categories; it required supplementation by a work that laid out the form and principles of outer intuition in their entirety" [GAP 542]. MFNS can thus serve "to supplement the Schematism and to complete the proof of the objective reality of the categories" [GAP 543]. In fact, Förster goes so far as to conclude from certain comments in Kant's Preface [MFNS 477-478] that MFNS is not intended to be "part of the metaphysical system" at all [GAP 538-539]. He infers this from the fact that Kant uses a rather unfortunate metaphor in describing the relation between MFNS and "general metaphysics ... (properly, transcendental philosophy)" [MFNS 478]: Kant says MFNS is like "a shoot springing indeed from [the] root [of general metaphysics] but only hindering its regular growth"; hence in MFNS Kant "plants this shoot apart ... [from] general metaphysics."

 

       The second problem is that there are at least five weighty objections to this aspect of Förster's interpretation. First, if MFNS served such a key role in the completion of the first Critique, then Kant would certainly have made a point of stressing this fact at some point in the second edition (published one year after MFNS); yet the second edition makes no reference to MFNS. Second, he would probably also have included these crucial new arguments themselves in the second edition (at least in summary form), since without them the arguments in the Critique are supposedly "insufficient"; yet no such arguments numbered among the many revisions Kant made to CPR in 1787. Third, the analogy of the "shoot" being entirely separable from the original plant, so that each can survive independently, would be wholly inappropriate if Förster's position is correct. Instead of emphasizing the sufficiency of CPR to stand on its own, as Kant intended, just the opposite would be true: the mother plant's roots (CPR) would not be able to survive once the shoot (MFNS) were transplanted. Fourth, Förster's accurate recognition of the need for a "completion" of the Schematism, with its exclusive emphasis on time, is misplaced. For he neglects the fact that this need is actually satisfied in the very next chapter of CPR, the Principles of Pure Understanding (and especially in the second edition Refutation of Idealism), where space is reintroduced into the system of knowledge, and its formal characteristics defined. Finally, in MFNS Kant clearly portrays his purpose as being, much like the purpose of his later Metaphysics of Morals (MM), not to provide a formal completion of CPR, but to provide material for its proper application—i.e., "instances (cases in concreto) to realize the concepts and propositions of [CPR]" [MFNS 478]. And this is not the task of Critique, but of Critically enlightened metaphysics.

 

        The mistaken character of Förster's interpretation of Kant's analogy of the "shoot" is made more obvious when we read MFNS 477-478, where Kant says MFNS's separation from the rest of the System can be done "without mistaking its origination from metaphysics or ignoring its entire outgrowth from the system of general metaphysics. Doing this does not affect the completeness of the system of general metaphysics" because this "separate metaphysics of corporeal nature" is now to be viewed as a smaller part (i.e., a subsystem) within "the larger system of metaphysics in general". Kant's point, in other words, is simply that, in keeping with his usual systematic method, he will divide his subject-matter into different "standpoints", and deal with each separately. The word "separately" here does not imply a complete detachment from his overall System, but simply a strategy of "divide and conquer".[4]?/span>Kant is saying that, instead of mixing together topics that adopt different standpoints, he prefers to treat them separately, with the understanding that they all remain under the "umbrella" of the general Perspective of the System (i.e., the Copernican Perspective, as described in the Preface to the second edition of CPR). Of course, this second problem gives rise to the need to determine more accurately the precise nature of the relationship Kant saw between MFNS and the rest of his System—a task I shall attempt to fulfill later in this essay.

 

        In addition to the problems associated with Förster's assumption that Kant would decide to make a fundamental revision of his entire System at such a late stage in his life, and with his assumption that MFNS fills a gaping hole in CPR's Schematism, a third problem now rears its ugly head: namely, Förster accepts the traditional view that Kant's overall purpose in OP was to construct his infamous "Transition". Because Kant says in his letter to Garve that his current project "concerns the ‘Transition from the metaphysical foundations of natural science to physics'", commentators have almost universally assumed he intended this, or something like it, to be the title of that work [see e.g., P8 281n]. But this completely ignores the fact that a significant portion of OP (e.g., most of fascicles one and seven) is concerned not with physics and theoretical reason but with theology and practical reason. It also ignores the fact that the first fascicle contains quite a few notes that are obviously ideas for prospective titles, presumably either for major divisions or for the work as a whole. "Transition ..." is only one of many titles that appear here, and was probably intended to apply to only one of the twelve divisions of OP (perhaps the twelfth [see OP 22.543]), since it does not aptly reflect the book's overall content. Indeed, even a cursory reading of OP reveals that Kant's interests were much broader than simply to establish such a Transition. This third problem, then, gives rise to the need to describe more fully the true purpose of OP.

 

        A fourth and final problem with Förster's interpretation is that it fails to give an adequate explanation for why Kant would describe the gap in his System as giving rise to "a pain like that of Tantalus". If the gap is really the recognition that his previous view of the relation between mathematics and physics is wrong, then this gap would not be tantalizing, but sickening, especially for someone who had devoted so much time and energy to the task of developing a System that rests (at least in part) on what would now be seen to be an incorrect view. The whole tenor of Kant's remarks to Garve suggests that the gap in question is tantalizing because it would complete the System for the first time, not because it would revise a System he had formerly thought to be complete. Providing an alternative interpretation that avoids this final problem will therefore require a more direct explanation of the implications of Kant's allusion to the myth of Tantalus.[5]

 

        In the remainder of this paper I shall offer another new explanation of the facts—one that enjoys the benefits of Förster's helpful suggestions, but provides solutions to the four problems raised above. I shall begin this task in the next section by examining some of Kant's long-term motivations for constructing a philosophical System; this will provide an important background against which the issues we are considering can be accurately viewed. §III will then provide a general overview of the architectonic relationships between the different books that constitute this System, including a new explanation of what Kant was aiming to accomplish in OP, thus solving the first three problems raised above. Finally, I shall demonstrate in §IV how this way of explaining the role of OP provides a perfect solution to the fourth problem, by revealing the significance of Kant's reference to the myth of Tantalus.

 

II. Kant's Critical Dreams as the Motive for a Philosophical System

 

        The word "tantalizing" may seem oddly out of place in a discussion of Kant's writing, so much of which is characterized by his often dry and abstract style of reasoning. This is true, at least, until we turn our attention to what is probably the most unjustly neglected work in Kant's corpus, his essay on Swedenborg's mystical experiences, entitled Dreams of a Spirit-Seer, Illustrated by Dreams of Metaphysics (DSS)—the work in which Kant compares the dangers of fanatical mysticism to those of speculative metaphysics. For its dual emphasis on the hope for mystical experiences and metaphysical knowledge of spirits, together with its paradoxical and sometimes shocking insistence that such hopes are bound to be disappointed, makes DSS one of the only books Kant wrote that can legitimately be said to tantalize the reader. Moreover, this same book gives us a glimpse of Kant's dawning awareness of a new, "Critical" way of doing philosophy. Inasmuch as DSS sets out for the first time a general problem that Kant devoted the rest of his life to solving, it can be regarded as the "seed" that eventually sprouted and grew into the "tree" of Critical philosophy.

 

        Although DSS is often interpreted as evidence of a radically "empiricist" stage in Kant's development, supposedly constituting a kind of Humean position, a careful examination of its contents reveals that his true intention is already to encourage a Critical attitude (though he did not yet call it by this name). While he comes down hard on the misuse of sensation and reason by spirit-seers and metaphysicians, respectively, when they regard their "dreams" as a source of knowledge [see S1 146], he clearly expresses his own dream that a properly balanced approach to both mysticism and metaphysics would someday emerge. As we shall see, Kant's Critical philosophy can be regarded as an attempt to construct a secure foundation for such an approach. Although the "tree" had matured by 1790, its "fruit" did not begin to ripen until shortly before 1798. For, as I shall argue in §III, OP was to be Kant's attempt to complete at long last the cycle that began with DSS, by bringing to full fruition the twofold task of Critical philosophizing. A brief overview of the contents of DSS will enable us to see more clearly what this fruit actually is.

 

        Before beginning his examination of the similarities between fanatical mysticism and speculative metaphysics, Kant hints at the Critical nature of the inquiry that is to follow, by asking two opposing questions, but offering a "third way" out. In the Preface to DSS he asks "Shall [the philosopher] wholly deny the truth of all the apparitions [eye-witnesses] tell about?" or "Shall he, on the other hand, admit even one of these stories?" In response, Kant advises philosophers to "hold on to the useful" [DSS 317-318(38)], thus avoiding both extremes. He then divides the main text into seven chapters, with the first four constituting the "Dogmatic" Part and the last three constituting the "Historical" Part. The correspondence between this division and the Critical philosophy he was soon to begin constructing in his mind is evident from the fact that Part One ends with a chapter on "Theoretical Conclusions", while Part Two ends with a corresponding chapter on "Practical Conclusions" [DSS 348(85),368(115)], thus foreshadowing, however dimly, the division between the first and second Critiques.

 

        Without going into the detailed arguments of these seven chapters at this point [but see P3 360-369], we can take note of some of the ways in which they adopt or prefigure views later defended in Kant's Critical philosophy. The first chapter of Part One begins with a discussion of what a spirit is or might be, and eventually appeals to freedom as the key determining principle [DDS 327n(52-53n)]: "Whatever in the world contains a principle of life, seems to be of immaterial nature. For all life rests on the inner capacity to determine one's self by one's own will power." The question of the possibility of spirits is also answered in an entirely Critical way: "The possibility of the existence of immaterial beings can ... be supposed without fear of its being disproved, but also without hope of proving it by reason" [323(48-49), emphasis added]. Kant's negative remarks about those such as Swedenborg, who actually claim to perceive spirits, are well known. What is not so well known is that Kant does not, in fact, go to the skeptical extreme that is typically attributed to him. Instead, he cautiously admits in Chapter Two that in an apparition, "delusion is mingled with truth", so that it tends to deceive a person "in spite of the fact that such chimeras may be based upon a true spiritual influence" [340(71-72), emphasis added]. Moreover, he develops in Chapter Two a complex theory of spiritual beings that focuses on the moral character of all spiritual reality: he argues that "the community of all thinking beings" is governed by "a moral unity, and a systematic constitution according to spiritual laws." Thus, "because the morality of an action concerns the inner state of the spirit", its effect can be fully realized not in the empirical world, but "only in the immediate communion of spirits" [336(65)]. There is no hint of skepticism here!

 

        In truly Critical fashion, however, Kant proceeds in Chapter Three to present what he calls an "Antikabala"—i.e., "A fragment of common philosophy aiming to abolish communion with the spirit-world" [DSS 342(74)]. Here he "renders entirely superfluous the deep conjectures of the preceding chapter" [347(82)] by demonstrating that the same experiences and knowledge-claims can be explained without making reference to anything beyond the empirical world. This skeptical chapter also contains Kant's harshest ridicule of those dogmatists who, like Swedenborg and like Kant himself just a few pages earlier, have been smitten with the "disease" [e.g., 340(71)] of seeing mystical or metaphysical visions. What is rarely acknowledged is that the fourth and final chapter of Part One takes a step back from the conflicting views defended in Chapters Two and Three, and seeks a balanced position between the foregoing dogmatic and skeptical perspectives. In other words, Kant never intended his words of skeptical ridicule to be taken as representing his true position. For he now requests us to check "the partiality of the scales of reason" by letting "the merchandise and the weights exchange pans" [348-349(85)]. By this he means first, that we must give up all former prejudices, whether skeptical or dogmatic [see 349(85-86)], and second, that if we do, we will discover that "[t]he scale of reason is not quite impartial", for it favors the pan "bearing the inscription ‘Hope for the Future'" [349(86)]. In other words, just as the Critical philosophy remains disjointed and incomplete until the first two Critiques are "crowned" by the third [cf. CJ 170]—i.e., by the Critique corresponding to the question, "What may I hope? [see e.g., CPR 833]—so also at this relatively early stage in his career, Kant had already come to recognize that "even those light reasons [of hope] ... outweigh the speculations of greater weight on the other side" [DSS 349(86); cf. CPR 617,795,811]. "This is the only inaccuracy [of the scales of reason] which I cannot easily remove, and which, in fact, I never want to remove" [DSS 349-350(86)]. Far from concluding on a note of skepticism, Chapter Four insists that, even though "in the scale of speculation they seem to consist of nothing but air", the dreams of spirit-seers (and metaphysicians) "have appreciable weight only in the scale of hope" [350(86-87)].

 

        Part Two begins with a chapter that recounts three stories concerning Swedenborg's spiritual powers. The next chapter then summarizes Swedenborg's own explanation of his "ecstatic journey through the world of spirits" [DSS 357(98)]; here Kant emphasizes that, in spite of being "utterly empty of the last drop of reason", the ideas of his "hero" have a striking resemblance to "the philosophical creation of my own brain" [359-360(101)]—i.e., to the theory of spirits proposed in Chapter Two, as Kant's own, independently-constructed position. He apologizes for wasting the reader's time, confesses he is still "in love" with metaphysics, and insists that metaphysics as a rational inquiry "into the hidden qualities of things" (i.e., speculative metaphysics) must be carefully distinguished from "metaphysics [as] the science of the boundaries of human reason" (i.e., metaphysics as Critique). This distinction then becomes the focus of the "practical conclusion" given in the third chapter of Part Two.

 

        In this final chapter of DSS, any doubt about the Critical (as opposed to dogmatic or skeptical) character of this treatise is resoundly dispelled. For example, after distinguishing between what we can know for science and what we need to know for wisdom, Kant emphasizes the importance of determining what is impossible to know, so that "the limits set to human reason by nature" can be recognized, in such a way that "even metaphysics will become ... the companion of wisdom" [DSS 368(115-116)]. In order to accomplish this task, he says, a new kind of philosophy is necessary: once philosophy "judges its own proceedings, and ... knows not only objects, but their relation to man's reason, then ... the boundary stones [will be] laid which in future never allow investigation to wander beyond its proper district" [368-369(116)]. The fact that the proper drawing of this boundary will exclude knowledge of spirits need cause no concern to either mystics or metaphysicians, as long as we recognize that "such knowledge is dispensable and unnecessary", because reason does not need to know such things [372(120)]: for "true wisdom is the companion of simplicity, and as, with the latter, the heart rules the understanding, it generally renders unnecessary the great preparations of scholars, and its aims do not need such means as can never be at the command of all men."

 

        Such comments make it abundantly clear that DSS served as a catalyst prodding Kant to set out a complete System of Critical philosophy. Indeed, a proper understanding of DSS, as forming a vital part of the Critical philosophy's historical context, is necessary for anyone who wishes to understand the general purpose of Kant's System, and so also, to interpret properly the purpose of OP. For if we keep in mind Kant's foundational comparison between the sensation-dreams of those who claim to have mystical experiences and the reason-dreams of those who claim to have metaphysical knowledge, then the fact that Kant saw DSS as requiring him not to give up his love of metaphysics, but rather to reform it (by applying to it the Critical method he was gradually coming to recognize), clearly implies that he also hoped for the day when the same Critical reform could be applied to the claims of mystics. In other words, the connection between mysticism and metaphysics represents not just a passing phase in Kant's early development, but an undercurrent that can be seen operating throughout his entire System. For if no other message comes through the pages of DSS, the notion that Kant saw the possibility of mystical experience and of metaphysical knowledge as standing or falling together, as two sides of the same coin, shines forth like the noonday sun.

 

III. The Opus Postumum as the "Grand Synthesis" of Kant's System

 

        Keeping in mind the foregoing account of one of Kant's most significant background motivations for constructing a philosophical System, we can now return to the problems introduced in §I, in hopes of finding a fresh solution to each. Solving the third problem, concerning the true role of OP in Kant's System, is one of the main concerns of the present essay. But any solution to that problem depends on how one solves the second problem, concerning the precise relationship between MFNS and Kant's other systematic works. I shall therefore begin by attempting to solve this second problem, pass from there to a consideration of the third and central problem, and conclude this section by considering the first problem, concerning the apparent change in Kant's view of mathematics in OP, versus that in MFNS. Solving the fourth problem, concerning the full significance of Kant's reference to the myth of Tantalus, will then be the task of the fourth and final section of this paper.

 

        In CPR 869 Kant explains that a complete system of metaphysics must include a speculative (i.e., theoretical) and a practical subsystem. He calls the former "metaphysics of nature" and the latter "metaphysics of morals". He then divides the former into four parts: "(1) ontology; (2) rational physiology; (3) rational cosmology; (4) rational theology" [874]. The first corresponds to "transcendental philosophy" itself, whereas the third and fourth are types of "transcendent physiology" [873-874]. This leaves the second as "the doctrine of nature" proper, which can itself be divided into "physica rationalis and psychologia rationalis" [874-875], in accordance with the distinction between inner and outer sense. If we take into consideration the corresponding twofold division of the Metaphysics of Morals (between inner morality, or virtue, and outer morality, or justice) [see e.g., MM 205], this means Kant originally intended the overall division of the Metaphysical wing of his System to cover four types of science: (1) science of body (i.e., rational physics); (2) science of mind (i.e., rational psychology); (3) science of right (i.e., rational politics); and (4) science of virtue (i.e., rational ethics). The architectonic relationship between these four branches of Metaphysical Science can be neatly expressed in the form of the following diagram:[6]

 

 

 

 

In CJ 170 Kant explains that, although a third Critique is necessary, "no separate [i.e., third] division of Doctrine is reserved for the faculty of judgment". Hence, no third book on metaphysics is necessary either: "with judgement Critique takes the place of Theory [i.e., of Metaphysics]; ... the whole ground will be covered by the Metaphysics of Nature and of Morals."

 

        In 1797 Kant published MM, explaining in the Preface [205] that this book expounds the "science of right" and the "science of virtue"—the third and fourth divisions of metaphysics cited above. He also explains that this book "forms a counterpart to the ‘Metaphysical Principles of the Science of Nature,' which have been already discussed in a separate work (1786)" [205]. This passage, which Förster unfortunately never mentions,[7]?/span>clearly indicates that Kant eventually came to regard MFNS as sufficient to serve as a sufficient realization of the "rational physics" aspect of his planned Metaphysics of Nature.[8]?/span>He was no doubt aware of the fact that MFNS does not contain a rational psychology, and had perhaps decided that the Metaphysics of Nature no longer needs the latter, since psychology is better pursued as an empirical science.[9]

 

        Reverting back to this more traditional view of the role of MFNS enables us not only to avoid the five objections raised in §I against Förster's problematic position, but also to see more order in the overall structure of Kant's System as it stood in 1798, when Kant wrote his letter to Garve. Pausing for a moment to specify the precise architectonic relationship between the books Kant had written up to this point may enable us to gain an invaluable clue as to the role of OP in Kant's System. The eight major works that make up the philosophical System Kant constructed during the thirty-one years following the publication of DSS can be classified into three types: those following the synthetic method (viz., the three Critiques); those companion volumes that support each Critique by following, for the most part, the analytic method (viz., PFM, FMM, and RBBR); and those developing the Metaphysical implications of Critical philosophy (viz., MFNS and MM). This classification of Kant's main systematic works, which I have defended at length elsewhere [see above, note 4], can be depicted in the following table:

 

 

 

 

The nature of the first two types of systematic works is relatively unproblematic, but that of the third type requires more explanation, especially since this table reveals what appears to be a gap in Kant's System as it stood in 1798.[10]

 

        The foregoing solution to the second problem raised in §I, together with this summary statement of the structure of Kant's System, now gives rise to a rather obvious hypothesis as to how the third problem can best be solved: perhaps the "gap" Kant mentions in his letter to Garve is identical to the gap represented by the question mark in the above table; and perhaps Kant's ultimate goal in writing OP was to fill this final gap by writing a General Metaphysics that adopts (like CJ) what I call the "judicial" standpoint.[11]?/span>In order for this hypothesis to carry much weight, two questionable points must be demonstrated: first, that Kant himself (in spite of his above-mentioned statement to the contrary) had at least considered the possibility of writing a third part to his Critical metaphysics; and second, that the contents of OP justify regarding it as such a "grand synthesis".

 

        We have already seen that Kant explicitly denies the need for a book that would occupy the empty square in the above table, for he asserts in CJ 170 that the third Critique will not require a corresponding book in the Doctrinal part of his System (i.e., in metaphysics proper). But let us take a closer look at how he describes this situation. A few pages later [176-179], he states that philosophy technically consists of only two parts, the theoretical and practical, and that a third part is necessary only for the purpose of completing the task of establishing the Critical foundations for metaphysics. He then explains [emphasis added] that "judgment" is connected with the faculty of "pleasure or displeasure" in order to "effect a transition from the faculty of pure knowledge, i.e., from the [theoretical] realm of the concepts of nature, to that of the [practical] concept of freedom, just as in its logical employment [i.e., within the theoretical system] it [i.e., judgment] makes possible the transition from understanding to reason."

 

        This interesting, dual use of the word "transition" gives us an important clue as to how best to interpret Kant's use of the same word (Übergang) in his letter to Garve. Here in 1790, Kant is stating that the vital transition within the first Critique (via the role of judgment in the Principles of Pure Understanding) is analogous to the vital transition in the Critical philosophy as a whole (via the Critique of Judgment), and that metaphysics itself requires no such transition. Instead, he tells us, the principles of judgment can, "when needful be annexed to one or [the] other [division of pure philosophy] as occasion requires" [CJ 168]. This usage is especially interesting in view of the fact that Förster demonstrates, on the basis not of this passage, but of evidence found in letters to and from Kiesewetter, that Kant's idea for writing the Transition from MFNS to physics "seems to go back at least to the year 1790" [GAP 536]. In other words, it seems that in the same year he published CJ, where he claimed that a third "transition" is possible, though not necessary for the completeness of his overall System, Kant promised his friend Kiesewetter that he would some day attempt to write a third transition after all!

 

        We now have evidence of three kinds of "transition", strongly suggesting that, when Kant uses this same word in his 1798 letter to Garve, he has in mind the extension of his "transitional" writings beyond CJ and RBBR to metaphysics itself. Such an interpretation requires us to assume that, between 1790 and 1798, Kant gradually changed his mind and came to see a third part of metaphysics no longer as an optional extra, but as an indispensable part of his System. Whereas in 1790 his friendly gesture to Kiesewetter committed him to writing only "a few sheets" concerning this Transition [quoted in GAP 536], by 1798 this same Transition was causing him to experience "a pain like that of Tantalus"! What could have caused such a change to occur? My suggestion is that in 1790 Kant could not bring himself to add yet another project to the already heavy workload he had cut out for himself. Many of his letters, even from earlier years, allude to his concern about whether or not he would live long enough to complete his current plan for a System [see also note 7, above]. As a 66 year old philosopher, who was just on the verge of completing his Critical propaedeutic to metaphysics, Kant knew in 1790 that a considerable amount of work still lay ahead if he wished to expound the System's metaphysical implications: RBBR, MM, and a more complete version of the Metaphysics of Nature still remained to be written, not to mention his various essays on history and politics. He already found it difficult to imagine living long enough to complete everything else he had planned, so how could he possibly commit himself to undertaking yet another major work? Yet, as each year went by and he completed more and more of his other projects, it became more and more likely that he would complete them all with some time and energy to spare; hence, it gradually dawned on him that this third Transition was too important to be merely "annexed" to other parts of the System.

 

        If we consider now the content of OP, we discover that the notes Kant left behind relate to far more than just a dry (and perhaps useless) Transition from MFNS to physics. This, surely, was to be part of the project he was working on in 1798; and it is important to recognize that this Transition would belong in a work on General Metaphysics, because such a book would pass from the theoretical standpoint of MFNS to the more concrete, judicial standpoint of physics. Yet many of Kant's notes relate to the practical side of his System, with the apparent intent of revealing how still another Transition takes place, this time passing from the practical standpoint of MM to the more concrete, judicial standpoint of real ethical judgments. For example, Kant has much to say in OP about the immediacy of the moral law, which can be regarded as the very "voice of God" in our heart, and about the personhood of the God in whom we intuit all things—even though this same God is still beyond the grasp of our theoretical knowledge. In such notes (found especially in the first and seventh fascicles) Kant seems to be coming closer than ever before to achieving the goal of describing the "Critical mysticism" which, as I have argued elsewhere [see P4 67-94 and P6 321-323], characterized his own attitude throughout his entire life.

 

        Our earlier discussion of DSS demonstrated that Kant first conceived of the laborious task of reforming metaphysics as part of a twofold problem. By 1798 Kant had satisfactorily accomplished his main task of thoroughly reforming the speculative tradition, not by disposing of metaphysics altogether, but by constructing a Critical metaphysics to put in its place. In the works composing the same philosophical System, he had also already made some significant progress in accomplishing his secondary task of thoroughly reforming the fanatical tradition, not by disposing of mysticism altogether, but by constructing a Critical mysticism to put in its place. For example, he argues in CJ that our experiences of beauty and purpose in art and nature reveal a depth of interaction between the noumenal and phenomenal worlds that provides a transcendental foundation for the kinds of experiences many mystics report of the "hand of God" in nature. Likewise, he argues in RBBR that religion gives us access to a power which, though arising out of morality, can alone fulfill the purpose of our moral nature, so long as we are willing to regard the moral law as the "voice of God", commanding us in the depths of our heart. What remained to be accomplished in 1798 was therefore the same for mysticism as it was for metaphysics: to bring the entire System to fruition by unifying all its diverse strands under a single, all-encompassing idea.

 

        Although a detailed analysis of the text of OP would be out of place at this point, the foregoing hypothesis as to how Kant viewed its contents can be further substantiated by examining some of the many notes (especially in the first fascicle) that record what seem to be ideas for prospective titles. Some of the most fitting ideas Kant considers are apparently intended as subtitles to the rather Nietzschian title, Zoroaster. For example, "Philosophy in the totality of its Conceptual Contents Gathered Together under One Principle" would emphasize Kant's intention to show how his entire System springs forth from the common root of immediate experience [see P6 108-110,118-141]; and "The Ideal of the Physically and at the Same Time Morally Practical Reason United in One Sense-Object" expresses explicitly his intention to synthesize the theoretical ("physical") and practical ("moral") standpoints in the judicial standpoint of sensible experience [quoted from OP in K1 607]. Such titles suggest that Kant's purpose was indeed to construct one final "grand synthesis" of his entire philosophical System —i.e., not just a synthesis of the Critical aspect of that system, which CJ had already accomplished, but a synthesis of its metaphysical aspect as well—an "idea of the whole" [see CPR xliv] that would bring together in one "Object" the doctrines of theoretical reason (physics and psychology) as well as those of practical reason (politics and ethics). This would indicate that Kant intended OP to be a General Metaphysics in a new form. The new factor, I believe, is precisely the judicial standpoint itself; inasmuch as it effects a synthesis between the theoretical and practical standpoints—i.e., between the exclusively theoretical "metaphysics of physics" (MFNS) and the exclusively practical "metaphysics of morals" (MM)—this judicial standpoint must be what Kant had in mind by his repeated references to the "highest standpoint of transcendental philosophy".[12]

 

        If my argument is correct, if the "gap" Kant refers to in his 1798 letter to Garve marks Kant's recognition that a third part is also necessary in metaphysics, just as it was in the Critical works, then the new position Kant adopts in OP reflects not so much a radical change of mind since writing CJ as a gradual increase in ambition. For Kant now saw before his eyes the possibility of composing a metaphysical Doctrine of the unity of all forms of human experience under one transcendental idea, the idea of "man" [e.g., OP 27] as the being in whom "God and the world"[13]?/span>are one. In other words, he was reaching out to grasp the opportunity of accomplishing the ultimate goal he had set for himself in DSS, by combining in one book the Critical metaphysics and the Critical mysticism. As such, Kant's hope of filling the tantalizing gap in his System must refer to the entirety of OP, which could perhaps most appropriately be regarded as an attempt to write what we could call his General Metaphysics of Experience. Since this interpretation fits in well with all the evidence we have been considering, I believe a detailed interpretation of OP along these lines would provide the best way to make sense out of its many diverse twists and turns. Thus, when Kant writes to Garve, saying "It must be completed, or else a gap will remain ...", the word "It" should be taken to refer back to "The project" as a whole, not only to the "Transition from MFNS to physics"; the latter forms only the part of that project that he happened to be working on at the time.

 

        The solutions I have now proposed to the second and third problems mentioned in §I make it quite easy to solve the first problem as well. The fact that Kant's attitude towards mathematics in OP is different from that in MFNS need not lead to Förster's rather extreme (and less than flattering) conjecture. A potential difficulty in solving this problem as Förster presents it is that he gives only a few hints as to what he believes Kant's new view actually is [GAP 548-550], explaining that a detailed study of the text "obviously ... cannot here be given" [GAP 551]. The passages Förster quotes from OP do seem to indicate that, whereas establishing "the mathematical foundations of physics" was an important part of MFNS, Kant now wishes to change his mind and say that mathematics will not be part of this new Transition from the Metaphysics of Nature to physics. From his brief description, it looks as if Förster's conviction that Kant did change his mind follows as a direct result of his view that MFNS is an extended footnote to CPR. Once we recognize, by contrast, that MFNS actually takes the place of the proposed Metaphysics of Nature in Kant's System, the passages Förster quotes can be readily interpreted in quite a different way.

 

        Kant's references to a new role for mathematics in OP simply indicate that, because a new standpoint is being adopted in OP, this work must also adopt a new way of looking at mathematics. MFNS had properly established from the theoretical standpoint the crucial role mathematics must play in the metaphysics of corporeal nature. The remaining need in OP was to examine from the judicial standpoint the being of nature (corporeal and incorporeal) as experienced (see note 12); and here, mathematics can be put aside as irrelevant. Thus, when Kant asks himself whether or not "the mathematical foundations of physics" is an issue that "belongs to the Transition", he is not asking (as Förster supposes) whether or not the MFNS view needs to be revised [see GAP 548-549]; rather, by this question, together with his negative answer, Kant is saying that, because this topic was already adequately dealt with from the theoretical standpoint in MFNS, there is no need for it to reappear when the standpoint changes to the judicial, as in the Transition section of OP. In other words, he is saying not only that the function of mathematics in MFNS and that of this new, non-mathematical Transition in OP are compatible, but also that they serve parallel functions in their respective standpoints. This parallelism can be further compared to the moral basis of MM, in the form of the conscience. By putting together these three branches of Kant's most mature conception of metaphysics, we can construct the following Table:

 

 

 

 

        We can now reconsider the passage from MFNS 470, quoted in §I (and in GAP 550), and see that it actually supports this solution to the problem. Kant does not say a Philosophy of Nature is absolutely impossible without mathematics. On the contrary, he says a general doctrine of this sort (i.e., a General Metaphysics of Experience) "may indeed be possible without mathematics" [MFNS 470]; only the Philosophy of Nature considered from the theoretical standpoint, as a doctrine of "determinate natural things"—i.e., as the particular "doctrine of body and doctrine of soul" (the first half being given in MFNS)—is impossible without considering the function of mathematics. Once we recognize that Kant intended OP to become the exposition of this General Metaphysics (and that, as such, it assumes a standpoint that synthesizes the theoretical and the practical standpoints), there is no need to regard the anti-mathematical "polemic" in OP as contradicting the mathematical emphasis in MFNS; for its subject-matter is to be considered from the standpoint of the judicial wing of Kant's System. OP is therefore bound to be misunderstood, even by the most meticulous specialist, if it is read through the closed and relatively bland spectacles of CPR and MFNS, rather than through the more open and fresh spectacles of CJ and RBBR, where Kant's Critical mysticism comes to the fore.

 

IV. The Tantalizing "Pain" of Kant's Final Dream

 

        The common supposition that OP contains the gropings of a formerly great philosopher as he enters senility is, as Förster rightly says [GAP 534], not supported by the actual contents of the text. But what has been ignored up to this point is that OP is also not a completely sober work. Rather, in these notes we see Kant, as it were, becoming intoxicated with the tantalizing prospects of finally bringing to completion the task he had set for himself more than thirty years before. Having established in §II the roots of Kant's motivations for constructing his System of Critical philosophy, and their connection with both mystical and metaphysical "dreams", we are now in a position to understand more fully why the gap he mentions tantalized him as his life drew to a close. As I argued in §III, the word "gap" must refer to the General Metaphysics of Experience, for which the eight completed books in his System (viz., CPR, PFM, and MFNS from the theoretical standpoint; CPrR, FMM, and MM from the practical standpoint; and CJ and RBBR from the judicial standpoint) had prepared the way. In other words, the gap is to be filled by the book OP was intended to be, whereas the Transition between MFNS and physics is the specific set of arguments within OP that Kant was working on in September of 1798. This means that, although Förster is right in refusing to identify the gap with the Transition, the intricate hypothesis he proposes to explain their difference is untenable.

 

        The main task of this final section will be to demonstrate the appropriateness of Kant's reference to the pain of Tantalus. Before doing so, however, I shall respond to two objections a supporter of Förster's interpretation might make to the view I have presented. The first is that Kant explicitly describes the gap as being in his "critical system", yet if we distinguish between the broad sense of "Kant's System", as referring to all his major philosophical works, and the narrow sense of these words, as referring only to the three Critiques, then the gap as I have interpreted it is not actually a part of the Critical System. The gap as Förster sees it, by contrast, is at the very heart of the first Critique itself! My response to this objection would be to say that Kant often uses the same term in both a narrow, technical sense, and elsewhere in a broad, looser sense.[14]?/span>Thus it is not unreasonable to suppose that Kant, whose whole way of doing philosophy had become known by 1798 as the "Critical philosophy", would use this phrase to include the works that set forth the metaphysical implications of the three Critiques. Although it would have been more accurate to say he saw a gap in the metaphysical application of his Critical philosophy, Kant's loose reference to the gap as being somewhere in the Critical philosophy need not imply the sudden recognition of any major defect in the Critiques themselves. Moreover, on Förster's interpretation, whereby the gap refers to the need for a new way of defending the objective validity of the categories and so also the connection between metaphysics and physics, the gap would be more appropriately described as a localized error in the first Critique, than as an empty hole in the overall System. Kant's wording implies that an entire book is missing, not just an argument within a book.

 

        A second objection is that my interpretation does not explain why Kant made no mention of the gap before 1798. Förster's key hypothesis rests on the assumption that this timing is a vital clue to the proper explanation of the facts. This is what leads him to conjecture that the publication of Selle's prize essay question prompted Kant to reconsider the role of mathematics in philosophy. There is, however, a much simpler and less presumptuous alternative. Kant's use of the word "gap" in his letter to Garve is most likely nothing more than an off-the-cuff remark, intended as part of his metaphorical reference to the myth of Tantalus.[15]?/span>So let us now examine that myth in more detail.

 

        Tantalus was a legendary Greek king who had found much favor in the sight of the gods. He was not only often entertained at their table, but "was himself on occasion their host" [R1 68]. However, at one point he did something that "offended them beyond pardon." In one version of the story, he serves the gods human flesh to test their omniscience, while in another he steals their nectar and serves it to his fellow humans. As punishment he is made to be "forever hungry and thirsty; he stands in a pool of water up to his chin, but whenever he tries to drink, it drops away from him. Overhead are boughs laden with fruit, but when he reaches for it, the wind blows it away" [R1 68].

 

        Förster's interpretation portrays Kant as knowing what needs to be done, just as Tantalus knew that food and drink would satisfy his hunger and thirst. However, it requires us to identify the unfulfilled desire with an object (a missing theory) which Kant could not at that point see clearly, whereas for Tantalus the everlasting torment was caused not so much by his lack of food and drink as such, but by their close proximity combined with their inaccessibility. If Kant was using his analogy with as much care as he normally did when speaking metaphorically [see A1 and T1], then the true referent of the "gap" must be something Kant both desired and saw before him, but was prevented from reaching (i.e., describing) by some uncontrollable force—a force that he says makes him "as it were mentally paralyzed". The word "gap" would then be carefully chosen to put a vivid picture before our eyes: the remaining book of his System is being compared to Tantalus' lips and hands; and the "pain" is caused on the one hand by the gap between these lips and the "water" of Kant's theoretical system (especially MFNS), and on the other hand by the gap between these hands and the "fruit" of Kant's practical system (especially MM). The word "gap" is simply an intentionally metaphorical description of the relation between the book he was then working on (viz., OP) and the rest of his philosophical System, as depicted in the following diagram:

 

 

 

Once this is recognized, it becomes clear that Kant had in fact referred to this gap on numerous previous occasions, except that elsewhere he normally referred to it literally (e.g., when discussing the parallels between metaphysics and Critique).

 

        Kant's famous letter to Garve was written in response to a letter in which Garve describes his long-standing and agonizing physical illness ("a malignant tumor of the face"), yet expresses surprise over the fact that he is still able to think clearly [KPC 250-251n]. Kant replies in a way that might seem rather unsympathetic. Immediately before the passage quoted at the beginning of this paper, Kant says: "I wonder though whether my own fate, involving a similar striving [i.e., "to work for the good of mankind"], would not seem to you even more painful, if you were to put yourself in my place" [251]. If Kant has the temerity to say such a thing in response to the sufferings of a long-standing friend, he must have been quite serious about his subsequent reference to Tantalus. In other words, he must have been feeling that, because his Critical philosophy had questioned the omniscience of the (false) gods of mankind (through the transcendental limits of knowledge established in CPR), or perhaps because one of its central goals was to offer the "nectar of the gods" to mankind (through the moral law established in CPrR), he was being punished by being kept from describing the dream he saw so clearly, right before his eyes.

 

        In any case, it is worth noting in conclusion what appears to be the one and only qualification Kant adds to his use of the analogy of Tantalus: whereas Tantalus was condemned to endure his torment forever, Kant stresses that his own tantalizing pain "is not a hopeless pain", because "[r]eason will not give up her demands for this". In fact, this may not be so much a qualification as a reminder of how appropriate the analogy is. From Tantalus' point of view, after all, the food and drink must have seemed to be well within his reach. A desirable object cannot tantalize us unless there is some hope that the goal can be reached. In the same way Kant's ideal of a "grand synthesis", in which his lifelong adherence to a Critical mysticism quite distinct from that of Swedenborg's could be described in all its glory, as the natural conclusion to his Critical metaphysics, must have seemed to Kant to be just within his reach, if only he could think clearly for a few more years. Once this is understood, however, we can see that his mental paralysis may have been caused not so much by senility (which normally has physical roots, after all), but by the simple fact that any attempt to describe the indescribable is bound to leave us speechless.

 

        Kant's reference to the hopefulness of reaching his goal only emphasizes the appropriateness of the comparison with Tantalus. For as it has turned out, Kant left the philosophical world with a text (OP) that will forever tantalize its readers precisely because it seems to put us within reach of a philosophical vision of the unity of Mind and Nature in their inner and outer aspects, yet recedes just beyond our reach when we try to describe that vision in words. Kant himself may have recognized the necessity of our continued failure in this regard. Indeed, before the dreams of DSS ever awakened in him the desire to construct a System of Critical philosophy, Kant explained in the conclusion of his Universal Natural History and Theory of the Heavens that "a great vision" of Nature is available to all who are open to it, even though the resulting experience cannot be fully described. His words, alluding to the tantalizing pain involved in trying to express the inexpressible—a pain he had felt for so much of his life[16]?/span>and hoped in 1798 finally to express—would perhaps have made a fitting conclusion to OP as well:

 

In the universal silence of Nature and in the calm of the senses the immortal soul's faculty of knowledge speaks an ineffable language and gives undeveloped concepts, which are indeed felt, but do not let themselves be described. [ANTH 367]

 

 


FOOTNOTES


 



[1]?/span>All references will be included in the text, using the abbreviations given in the Bibliogra­phy.

 

[2]?/span>GAP 533-555. I would like to thank Eckart Förster for kindly providing me not only with an offprint of his stimulating article, but also with an early draft of his translation of selections from OP. The published version of his translation had not yet appeared at the time I wrote this article.

 

[3]?/span>As early as the Preface to the first edition of CPR [Axxi] Kant announces that he hopes to produce "a system of pure (speculative) reason ... under the title Metaphysics of Nature" [see also MM 205; CJ 170,171]. He then says it will adopt the method of "analysis", as compared to the synthetic method of the Critique. This distinction can be used to draw up a schematic map of the nine basic works in Kant's System, as I have done elsewhere [see below, note 4]. As we shall see in §III below, this systematic schema seems to have dawned on Kant only gradually, though the basic distinction between Critique as synthetic and metaphysics as ana­lytic remained virtually unchanged throughout his writings [see P6 91-103].

 

[4]?/span>I made a first attempt to describe the systematic, perspectival relationships between the differ­ent parts of Kant's System in P1 266-288. That argument was then revised and published as Chapter III of P6. The present paper is in part a further defense and elaboration of the reasons for placing MFNS and OP in the positions proposed in these previous publications.

 

[5]?/span>Förster is aware of the importance of taking into consideration Kant's reference to the myth of Tantalus, for he mentions it on several occasions [GAP 533,537,549,551]. However, the most he ever says in the way of explaining why his description of the gap makes it appropriate to compare it with the pain of Tantalus is that in September of 1798 "Kant could only see that, but not how, the Transition must achieve this goal" [GAP 537]—i.e., the goal of filling the gap left by his supposed recognition of the inadequacy of MFNS. Yet such a perplexing situation would not be consistent with the type of tantalizing "pain" symbolized by the myth in question. As we shall see in §IV, the myth alludes to a pain caused by a desire of which both the cause (the "that") and the means of satisfaction (the "how") are fully known, but whose fulfillment is pre­vented by some extraneous factors that are out of the individual's control. The alternative I shall suggest is perhaps most appealing in view of how perfectly it fits Kant's analogy.

 

[6]?/span>This diagram conforms perfectly to the logical structure of a "second level analytic relation", as described in Chapter 11 of P7. A diagram with exactly the same pattern is used in P6 83 to depict the relations between Kant's four Principles of Pure Understanding [see Figure 4.4].

 

[7]?/span>Instead, Förster argues that Kant did not regard MFNS as part of the proposed Metaphysics of Nature, citing as his main evidence the fact that Kant refers in the second edition Preface of CPR (written in 1787, one year after MFNS) to the need for a "metaphysics of nature" [CPR xliii; see GAP 538]. However, what Kant actually says in that passage is as follows: "I must be careful with my time if I am to succeed in my proposed scheme of providing a metaphysics of nature and of morals ..." [CPR xliii]. The words "to succeed in my proposed scheme" could easily be interpreted to mean "to complete the scheme I have already started". This, at least, makes for a more reasonable explanation than Förster's conjecture that MFNS was intended to complete a missing link in the argument of CPR.

 

[8]?/span>That this was not Kant's original conception of the function of this book is indicated in a let­ter to Sch§tz (13 September 1785), where Kant describes MFNS "as a chapter containing the concrete application of the Metaphysics of Nature ... This preliminary work is given out in ad­vance because the metaphysic must retain its character as entirely pure, whereas here an empiri­cal concept is presupposed" [quoted in P8 277; cf. KPC 119]. But MM 205 seems to leave no alternative ex­cept that Kant at some point changed his mind on this issue, perhaps in order to preserve the integrity of the architectonic structure of his System (see below).

 

[9]?/span>This, at least, is Paulsen's interpretation in P8 287: "psychology according to Kant is an ex­pe­riential science, and as such ..., does not belong to philosophy in the proper sense of the word." And Kant himself, in MFNS 471, appears to be repealing his commitment to include rational psychology in the Metaphysics of Nature when he writes: "the empirical doc­trine of the soul ... can ... never become anything more than a historical ... natural doctrine of the internal sense, i.e., a natural description of the soul, but not a science of the soul ... This is the reason why in the title of this work ... we have employed ... the general name of natural science"—i.e., rather than calling it merely the Metaphysical Foundations of Rational Physics.

 

               A further explanation for Kant's failure to write the second half of the Metaphysics of Nature (i.e., rational psychology) is as follows. Aside from ontology (transformed into transcendental philoso­phy in CPR) and rational physics (as transformed in MFNS) there are three remain­ing parts in Kant's description of the contents of the Metaphysics of Nature: rational psychol­ogy, rational cosmology and rational theology. These are in fact the three ideas of reason which, in the Dialectic of CPR, are regarded as illusory when viewed from the theoretical standpoint. Thus it is not surprising that Kant did not include them in that work. However, filling the metaphysical gap left by the illusory character of any theoretical treatment of these ideas may well have been part of the purpose of OP—i.e., to discuss these three remaining topics from their proper, "judicial" standpoint [see note 11].

 

[10]?/span>In P1 284-288 and P6 91-103 the table given here appears in the form of a rather complex dia­gram (using three crosses, connected by a triangle). The only three debatable points in this analy­sis of Kant's architectonic are: (1) the placement of MFNS, which I have de­fended above; (2) the placement of RBBR, which I have defended at length in P5 [see also P6 319-321]; and (3) the filling of the one remaining gap in the table, which is the main focus of the present essay.

 

[11]?/span>In some earlier publications I referred to this third standpoint (that which the gap in the fore­going table shares with CJ and RBBR) as the "empirical" standpoint, because empirical laws of nature (and the like) are taken into consideration much more seriously here than in rea­soning based on the theoretical or practical standpoints. This proved to be rather misleading, how­ever, since (1) its use in this context is different from its use in the important transcendental-empirical distinction; and (2) it could be confused with the empirical perspective within CPR (a potential equivocation Kant himself recognizes in CJ 178-179). I now refer to the standpoint of CJ as "judicial" (i.e., pertaining to judgment) in hopes of clarifying that its transcendental status is preserved, and that its scope is broader than the empirical perspective of CPR.

 

[12]?/span>On this basis we can now answer the second question asked in the first para­graph of this es­say: MFNS and OP both provide a kind of "transition to physics"; but the former is primarily a theoretical transition from CPR to physics, whereas the latter is an all-inclusive judicial transi­tion between physics and morals that includes the former as one of its many "sub-transitions". Kant had said in CJ that the aesthetic judgment needs no metaphysics because it is non-cognitive. Understood in this light, his repeated references to the unifying "sense-object" in OP provide yet another indication of the judicial character of the transitions it effects. The Meta­physics of Nature and the Metaphysics of Morals can be scientific because they are cognitive, but judicial metaphysics, like the judicial Critique, must focus more directly on our imme­diate experience. This may be why Kant at first said there is no need for such a (quasi-)science, and also why it turned out to be so difficult to express once he began to compose it.

 

[13]?/span>Kant first mentions this twofold idea in the very first line of OP [21.9], and repeatedly returns to it throughout the first and seventh fascicles. The unity of God and Nature in a human being's own experience of personhood appears to be the most fundamental point at which Kant's Critical metaphysics and his Critical mysticism become one.

 

[14]?/span>A good example is his twofold use of terms such as "a priori" and "transcendental" [see P2 176 and P6 107-111].

 

[15]?/span>This is supported by the fact, mentioned by Förster in GAP 537, that the very earliest refer­ences to a "gap" appear in the notes Kant made in preparation for writing his 1798 letter to Garve.

 

[16]?/span>Indeed, I would suggest that this problem of ineffability (almost enjoyed in 1755!) only began to impress Kant as a pain in 1766, when the seriousness of the gap between genuine knowledge and the mystical/metaphysical dreams of human sensation/reason first became clear to him [see ?/span>II]. Initial denial of this painful aspect of the gap may be one explanation for the rather flippant posture Kant adopted in DSS. He was also, of course, trying to get over the pain of having Swedenborg totally ignore the serious letter of inquiry Kant had sent him several years before.

 

 

 

BIBLIOGRAPHY 

I. Kant’s Works

ANTH: Allgemeine Naturgeschichte und Theorie des Himmels oder Versuch von der Verfassung und dem mechanischen Ursprunge des ganzen Weltgebaudes, nach Newtonischen Grundsatzen abgehandelt, 1755; in Kants gesammelte schriften (Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 1902-)—hereafter Akademie—vol.1, pp.215-368, my translation.

DSSDreams of a Spirit-Seer (1766), tr. E. Goerwitz (London: Swan Sonnenschein & Co., 1900). Page numbers to this and other works by Kant (except CPR and KPC) refer to the corresponding Akademie volume. Since the Goerwitz translation does not provide the Akademie pagination, references will include the pagination of the translation in parentheses.

CPRCritique of Pure Reason, tr. N. Kemp Smith (London: Macmillan, 1933). Page numbers refer to the second edition pagination, except where the material is unique to the first edition, in which case the number will be preceded by “A?

PFMProlegomena to Any Future Metaphysics (1783).

FMMFoundations of the Metaphysics of Morals (1785).

MFNS:Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science (1786), tr. J. Ellington (New York: The Bobbs-Merrill Co., Inc., 1970).

CPrRCritique of Practical Reason (1788).

CJCritique of Judgment (1790), tr. J.C. Meredith (Oxford: Clarendon, 1952).

RBBR: Religion Within the Bounds of Bare Reason (1793).

MMMetaphysics of Morals (1797), Part I tr. J. Ladd in The Metaphysical Elements of Justice (New York: The Bobbs-Merrill Co., Inc., 1965).

OPOpus Postumum (notes written mostly between 1796 and 1803, collected in volumes 21 and 22 of the Akademie edition). Translations of Kant’s Opus Postumum are my own, though I have made some use of E. Förster’s translation (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993)—see above, note 2.

KPCKant’s Philosophical Correspondence 1759-99, tr. A. Zweig (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1967). Page numbers refer to the translation. 

II. Other Sources

A1: Axelsen, Diana E., “Kant’s Metaphor For Persons and Community? Philosophy & Theology III.4 (Summer 1989), pp.301-321.

GAP: Eckart Förster , “Is There ‘A Gap?in Kant’s Critical System?? Journal of the History of Philosophy 25.4 (October 1987).

K1: Kemp Smith, Norman, A Commentary to Kant’s “Critique of Pure Reason?/i>2 (London: Macmillan & Co. Ltd., 1923[1918]).

P1:  Stephen Palmquist, “The Architectonic Form of Kant’s Copernican Logic? Metaphilosophy 17.4 (October 1986), pp.266-288.

P2:  ?? “Knowledge and Experience—An Examination of the Four Reflective ‘Perspectives?in Kant’s Critical Philosophy? Kant-Studien 78.2 (1987), pp.170-200.

P3:  ?? “Kant’s Critique of Mysticism: (1) The Critical Dreams? Philosophy & Theology 3.4 (Summer 1989), pp.355-383. This article was unfortunately published with several hundred gross typographical/editorial errors (including numerous missing and duplicated lines), rendering the text virtually unintelligible. Interested readers may consult the original version on my web site, located at: http://www.hkbu.edu.hk/~ppp/hp.html.

P4: ?? “Kant’s Critique of Mysticism: (2) The Critical Mysticism? Philosophy & Theology 4.1 (Fall 1989), pp.67-94.

P5:     ?? “Does Kant Reduce Religion to Morality?? Kant-Studien 83.2 (1992), 129-148.

P6:  ?? Kant’s System of Perspectives (Lanham, MD: University Press of America, 1993).

P7: ??, The Tree of Philosophy3 (Hong Kong: Philopsychy Press, 1995).

P8: Paulsen, Freidrich, Immanuel Kant: Sein Leben und seine Lehre, 1898. Tr. J.E. Creighton and A. Lefèbvre as Immanuel Kant: His Life and Doctrine (New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons, 1902).

R1:  H.J. Rose, Gods & Heroes of the Greeks (New York: The World Publishing Company, 1958).

S1:  Frank Sewall, “Introduction?in Goerwitz’s translation of DSS.

T1: Tarbet, David W., “The Fabric of Metaphor in Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason? Journal of the History of Philosophy 6 (1968), pp.257-270.

 

 

---

This etext is based on a prepublication draft of the published version of this essay.

 

Send comments to: StevePq@hkbu.edu.hk

 

My Web Counter identifies you as visitor number

 

http://counter.digits.com/wc/-d/4/StevePalmquist_sPublishedArticles

 

to this page, last updated on 29 March 2011. Please come again!

 

Back to the listing of Steve Palmquist's published articles.

 

Back to the main map of Steve Palmquist's web site