Skip to main content

Anger Issues: The Nature and Complexity of Emotions and Emotional Valence

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Dark Side: Philosophical Reflections on the “Negative Emotions”

Abstract

Our analysis starts with a definition of emotions and how they work. We illustrate our discussion with examples, primarily related to anger. We devote special attention to the feelings that characterize our emotional experience, relying on ‘alexithymia’, a clinical condition, to argue for a perceptual theory of emotion in which emotional feelings are the means by which we identify and recognize our emotions. Finally, we consider the role of valence in the mechanism of the emotions, i.e. the way in which emotions are generated, lead to the motivation to end/modify a situation that is perceived as negative or to prolong/reiterate a situation that is perceived as positive, and produce behaviours congruent with this motivation. Here we show that because emotions have multiple and ambiguous valences, one cannot rely on valence to determine, in abstraction, what motivation and behaviour a given emotion will trigger.

Authors are listed in reverse alphabetical order; this article was truly cooperative.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 99.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    This sense of the term ‘affective’ played an important – if sometimes ambiguous – role in the psychological lexicon starting from the second half of the nineteenth century onwards (cf. Wassmann 2008).

  2. 2.

    The overlap in notions such as ‘temperament’ and ‘character’ provides insight into the common psychological lexicon. The notion of ‘temperament’ preceded that of ‘character’ in the history of philosophy, medicine and psychiatry. It indicated innate and constitutive factors that tacitly drive individual behaviour and emotional dispositions. The notion of ‘character’ instead indicated the factors that predispose people to react in certain ways: habits, individual choices and environmental conditioning which influence temperament. In the contemporary literature, the notions of ‘temperament’ and ‘character’ have not disappeared altogether from the psychological lexicon, but form part of the construct of personality. For an overview, cf. e.g. Ewald 1924; Strelau 1998; Kagan and Snidman 2004.

  3. 3.

    The issue of whether knowledge is always required for appraisal and of when it is/is not part of the appraisal process was the subject of a thorny dispute that exploded in the ’80s (also as a result of the publication of Zajonc’s article Feeling and Thinking in 1980) and still continues today. For a brief review cf. Prinz 2004, p. 33ff.

  4. 4.

    In philosophy the issue of whether an emotion is or is not appropriate is most often considered in relation to a moral context, that is, whether specific emotions are or are not morally appropriate in specific contexts. For a discussion of what ‘appropriateness’ exactly means in this context cf. e.g. D’Arms and Jacobson 2000.

  5. 5.

    Already Darwin [1872] (1965) regarded postures, movements, bodily and facial expressions as equivalent reactions to specific emotions – i.e., in more contemporary language, as equivalent behavioural patterns corresponding to an emotion. In his view, the fact that humans and animals share similar reactions to the same emotions is, on the one hand, a sign that they are innate or instinctive and, on the other hand, further proof that humans and animals share a common phylogenetic origin. Most notoriously, it was Paul Ekman who, following Darwin, Tomkins (1962, 1963) and Frijda’s line of research (Frijda 1986), argued that emotions are ‘affect programs’ (he takes this notion from Tomkins), i.e. evolutionarily determined responses to environmental situations characterized by a number of distinctive features, which include physiological changes, facial expressions, assessments, behavioural reactions and dispositions (cf. e.g. Ekman 2003).

  6. 6.

    In fact, emotions give rise to spontaneous and immediate action tendencies that are part of an emotional episode. Skeletal and muscular signals also derive from action programs elicited by emotions.

  7. 7.

    We get to experience our emotions through the feelings that characterize them. This does not mean, however, that we cannot have emotions in the absence of bodily feelings. Indeed, as suggested for example by Damasio, the brain centres typically associated with the bodily changes that occur during emotion episodes can also be activated in the absence of bodily signals just by remembering the bodily changes that occurred in previous occasions. This mechanism is called an “as-if-loop” (Damasio 1994, p. 155ff).

  8. 8.

    Given their emotional impairment, alexithymics even have difficulties with tasks that indirectly involve emotions, e.g. tasks that require empathy, mindreading capacities or, more generally, social competencies. However, they exhibit normal intelligence as well as fully developed linguistic and logical capacities. Cf., i.a., Wotschak and Klann-Delius 2013.

  9. 9.

    Cf. e.g. the list of properties that identify positive and negative emotions given by Solomon, Stone (2002, p. 418); some of the features reported in this list were omitted on purpose from the example and will be considered below.

  10. 10.

    These criteria for assessing whether an emotion is positive or negative represent a simplified summary of the review of various conceptions of valence proposed by Prinz 2004, pp. 167ff and Colombetti 2005. These criteria are uniquely of a psychological kind. In fact, emotions can be classified as positive or negative also from a moral/social point of view – i.e. depending on whether they foster or hinder moral/prosocial actions. These two criteria can easily give rise to contradictory outcomes: an emotion that is positive from a psychological viewpoint can be negative from a moral or from a social viewpoint. On the distinction between these two criteria cf. e.g. Ben-Ze’ev (2000, pp. 103) and Kristjánsson (2003, p. 356ff).

  11. 11.

    The mechanism of emotions as we have described it here should be considered a subpart of the ‘machinery’ mentioned by Damasio.

References

  • Al-Shawaf, L., Conroy-Beam, D., Asao, K., & Buss, D. M. (2015). Human emotions: An evolutionary psychological perspective. Emotion Review, 1–14. https://doi.org/10.1177/1754073914565518.

  • Arnold, M. B. (1960). Emotion and personality. Psychological aspects (Vol. 1). New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ben-Ze’ev, A. (2000). The subtlety of emotions. Cambridge/London: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Clore, G. L. (1994). Why emotions require cognition. In P. Ekman & R. J. Davidson (Eds.), The nature of emotion: Fundamental questions (pp. 181–191). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clore, E. L., & Ortony, A. (2000). Cognition in emotion: Always, sometimes, or never? In R. D. Lane & L. Nadel (Eds.), Cognitive neuroscience of emotion (pp. 24–25). Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clore, G. L., & Ortony, A. (2008). Appraisal theories: How cognition shapes affect into emotion. In M. Lewis, J. M. Haviland-Jones, & L. Feldman Barrett (Eds.), Handbook of emotions (pp. 628–642). New York: The Guilford Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Colombetti, G. (2005). Appraising valence. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 12(8–10), 103–126.

    Google Scholar 

  • Craig, A. D. (2002). How do you feel? Interoception: The sense of the physiological condition of the body. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 3, 655–666.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craig, A. D. (2008). Interoception and emotion: A neuroanatomical perspective. In M. Lewis, J. M. Haviland-Jones, & L. Feldman Barrett (Eds.), Handbook of emotions (3rd ed., pp. 272–288). New York/London: The Guilford Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • D’Arms, J., & Jacobson, D. (2000). The moralistic fallacy: On the ‘Appropriateness’ of emotions. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 61(1), 65–90.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Damasio, A. R. (1994). Descartes’ error: Emotion, reason, and the human brain. New York: Avon books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Damasio, A. R. (2000). A second chance for emotion. In R. D. Lane & L. Nadel (Eds.), Cognitive neuroscience of emotions (pp. 12–23). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwin, C. [1872](1965). The expression of the emotions in man and animals. Chicago/London: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deigh, J. (2004). Primitive emotions. In R. C. Solomon (Ed.), Thinking about feeling: Contemporary philosophers on emotions (pp. 9–27). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dellantonio, S., & Pastore, L. (2017). Internal perception. The role of bodily information in concepts and word mastery. Berlin: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dixon, T. (2003). From passions to emotions: The creation of a secular psychological category. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dixon, T. (2012). “Emotion”: The history of a keyword in crisis. Emotion Review, 4(4), 338–344.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ekman, P. (1999). Basic emotions. In T. Dalgleish & M. Power (Eds.), Handbook of cognition and emotion (pp. 45–60). Chichester: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ekman, P. (2003). Emotions revealed: Recognizing faces and feelings to improve communication and emotional life. New York: Times Book.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elster, J. (1999). Strong feelings. Emotion, addiction and human behavior. Cambridge. MA: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ewald, G. (1924). Temperament und Charakter. Berlin/Heidelberg: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fredrickson, B. L., & Branigan, C. I. (2001). Positive emotions. In T. J. Mayne & G. A. Bonanno (Eds.), Emotions: Current issues and future directions (pp. 123–151). New York/London: The Guilford Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fredrickson, B. L., & Cohn, M. A. (2004). Positive emotions. In M. Lewis, J. M. Haviland-Jones, & L. Feldman Barrett (Eds.), Handbook of emotions (pp. 777–796). New York: The Guilford Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frijda, N. H. (1986). The emotions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frijda, N. H. (1994). Varieties of affect: Emotion and episodes, moods and sentiments. In P. Ekman & R. J. Davidson (Eds.), The nature of emotion: Fundamental questions (pp. 59–67). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gervais, M., & Fessler, D. (2017). On the deep structure of social affect: Attitudes, emotions, sentiments, and the case of “contempt”. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 40, E225. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0140525X16000352.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldie, P. (2002). Emotions, feelings and intentionality. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 1, 235–254.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldsmith, H. H. (1994). Parsing the emotional domain form a developmental perspective. In P. Ekman & R. J. Davidson (Eds.), The nature of emotion: Fundamental questions (pp. 68–73). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grabe, H. J., Spitzer, G., & Freyberger, H. J. (2001). Alexithymia and the temperament and character model of personality. Psychotherapy and Psychosomatics, 70, 261–267.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Isen, A. M. (2004). Positive affect and decision making. In M. Lewis, J. M. Haviland-Jones, & L. Feldman Barrett (Eds.), Handbook of emotions (pp. 417–435). New York: The Guilford Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • James, W. (1884). What is an emotion? Mind, 9(34), 188–205.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kagan, J., & Snidman, N. (2004). The long shadow of temperament. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kristjánsson, K. (2003). On the very idea of “negative emotions”. Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour, 33(4), 351–364.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Krystal, H. (1988). Integration and self-healing: Affect, trauma, alexithymia. Hillsdale: The Analytic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lambie, J. A., & Marcel, A. J. (2002). Consciousness and the varieties of emotion experience: A theoretical framework. Psychological Review, 119, 219–259.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lane, R. D., & Schwartz, G. E. (1987). Levels of emotional awareness: A cognitive-developmental theory and its application to psychopathology. The American Journal of Psychiatry, 144, 133–143.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lane, R. D., Ahern, G. L., Schwartz, G. E., & Kaszniak, A. W. (1997). Is alexithymia the emotional equivalent of blindsight? Biological Psychiatry, 42, 834–844.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lane, R. D., Weihs, K. L., Herring, A., Hishaw, A., & Smith, R. (2015). Affective agnosia: Expansion of the alexithymia construct and a new opportunity to integrate and extend Freud’s legacy. Neuroscience and Biobehavioral Reviews, 55, 594–611.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lange, C. G. [1885] (1912). The mechanism of the emotion. In B. Rand (Ed.), The classical psychologists (pp. 672–684). Boston: Houghton Mifflin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lange, C.G. [1885] (1922). The emotions. A psychophysiological study. In K. Dunlap (Ed.), The emotions. Volume 1 (pp. 32–90). Baltimore: Williams & Wilkins Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lazarus, R. S. (1991). Emotion and adaptation. New York/Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lazarus, R. S. (1994a). The stable and the unstable in emotion. In P. Ekman & R. J. Davidson (Eds.), The nature of emotion: Fundamental questions (pp. 79–85). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lazarus, R. S. (1994b). The stable and the unstable in emotion. In P. Ekman & R. J. Davidson (Eds.), The nature of emotions: Fundamental questions (pp. 208–214). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • LeDoux, J. E. (1996). The emotional brain. New York: Simon and Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lemerise, E. A., & Dodge, K. A. (2008). The development of anger and hostile interactions. In M. Lewis, J. M. Haviland-Jones, & L. Feldman Barrett (Eds.), Handbook of emotions (pp. 730–741). New York: The Guilford Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lyons, W. (1980). Emotion. Cambridge/London: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mac Laren, K. (2006). Emotional disorder and the mind/body problem: A case study of alexithymia. Chiasmi International, 8, 139–155.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M. C. (2003). Upheavals of thought: The intelligence of emotions. Cambridge: Cambrigde University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ortony, A., Clore, G. L., & Collins, A. (1988). The cognitive structure of emotions. Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Plamper, J. (2012). Geschichte und Gefühl. Grundlagen der Emotionsgeschichte. München: Siedler.

    Google Scholar 

  • Primmer, J. (2013). Understanding the dimensional nature of alexithymia. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 20, 111–131.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prinz, J. J. (2004). Gut reactions: A perceptual theory of emotion. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ratcliffe, M. (2008). Feelings of being. Phenomenology, psychiatry, and the sense of reality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ridderinkhof, R. K. (2017). Emotion in action: A predictive processing perspective and theoretical synthesis. Emotion Review, 9(4), 319–325. https://doi.org/10.1177/1754073916661765.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roseman, I. J., & Smith, C. A. (2001). Appraisal theory. Overview, assumptions, varieties, controversies. In K. R. Scherer, A. Schorr, & T. Johnstone (Eds.), Appraisal processes in emotion: Theory, methods, research (pp. 3–19). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scarantino, A. (2012). How to define emotions scientifically. Emotion Review, 4(2), 358–368.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scherer, K. R. (1994). An emotion’s occurrence depends on the relevance of an event to the organism’s goal/need hierarchy. In P. Ekman & R. J. Davidson (Eds.), The nature of emotion: Fundamental questions (pp. 227–231). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schuetze, P. (2019). The moral adequacy of emotions. Rivista internazionale di Filosofia e Psicologia, 10(1), 33–48. https://doi.org/10.4453/rifp.2019.0003

  • Sifneos, P. E. (1972). Short-term psychotherapy and emotional crisis. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Solomon, R. C. (2004). Emotions, thoughts, and feelings: Emotions as engagements with the world. In R. C. Solomon (Ed.), Thinking about feeling: Contemporary philosophers on emotions (pp. 76–88). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Solomon, R. C., & Stone, L. D. (2002). On “positive” and “negative” emotions. Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour, 32, 417–435. https://doi.org/10.1111/1468-5914.00196.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stephan, A. (2017a). Moods in layers. Philosophia, 45, 1481–1495.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stephan, A. (2017b). On the adequacy of emotions and existential feelings. Rivista internazionale di Filosofia e Psicologia, 8(1), 1–13. https://doi.org/10.4453/rifp.2017.0001.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strelau, J. (1998). Temperament. A psychological perspective. New York/Boston/Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, G. J., Bagby, R. M., & Parker, J. D. A. (1997). Disorders of affect regulation. Alexithymia in medical and psychiatric illness. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tomkins, S. S. (1962). Affect, imagery and consciousness (Vol. 1). New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tomkins, S. S. (1963). Affect, imagery and consciousness (Vol. 2). New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tugade, M. M., & Fredrickson, B. L. (2007). Regulation of positive emotions: Emotion regulation strategies that promote resilience. Journal of Happiness Studies, 8(3), 311–333.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wassmann, C. (2008). Physiological optics, cognition and emotion: A novel look at the early work of Wilhelm Wundt. Journal of the History of Medicine and Allied Sciences, 64(2), 213–249.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wassmann, C. (2017). Forgotten origins, occluded meanings: Translation of emotion terms. Emotion Review, 9(2), 163–171.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wotschak, C., & Klann-Delius, G. (2013). Alexithymia and the conceptualization of emotions: A study of language use and semantic knowledge. Journal of Research in Personality, 47(5), 514–523. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jrp.2013.01.011.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zajonc, R. B. (1980). Feeling and thinking. Preferences need no inference. American Psychologist, 35(2), 151–175.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Sara Dellantonio .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2021 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Pastore, L., Dellantonio, S. (2021). Anger Issues: The Nature and Complexity of Emotions and Emotional Valence. In: Giacomoni, P., Valentini, N., Dellantonio, S. (eds) The Dark Side: Philosophical Reflections on the “Negative Emotions”. Studies in the History of Philosophy of Mind, vol 25. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-55123-0_14

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics