Hostname: page-component-7c8c6479df-ph5wq Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-03-28T09:25:59.628Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Do the folk need a meta-ethics?

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  17 May 2018

Shivam Patel
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, University of Pittsburgh, Pittsburgh, PA 15260. smp119@pitt.eduhttp://www.philosophy.pitt.edu/person/shivam-patel-0
Edouard Machery
Affiliation:
Department of History and Philosophy of Science, and Center for Philosophy of Science, University of Pittsburgh, Pittsburgh, PA 15260. machery@pitt.eduhttp://www.edouardmachery.com

Abstract

Stanford argues that cooperators achieve and maintain correlated interaction through the objectification of moral norms. We first challenge the moral/non-moral distinction that frames Stanford's discussion. We then argue that to the extent that norms are objectified (and we hold that they are at most objectified in a very thin sense), it is not for the sake of achieving correlated interaction.

Type
Open Peer Commentary
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2018 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Balliet, D., Mulder, L. B. & Van Lange, P. A. (2011) Reward, punishment, and cooperation: A meta-analysis. Psychological Bulletin 137:594615.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Foot, P. (1972) Morality as a system of hypothetical imperatives. The Philosophical Review 81:305–16.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goodwin, G. P. & Darley, J. M. (2008) The psychology of meta-ethics: Exploring objectivism. Cognition 106:1339–66. Available at: http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2007.06.007.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hume, D. (1738/1975) A treatise of human nature, ed. Selby-Bigge, L. A., rev. Nidditch, P. H., Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Kelly, D., Stich, S., Haley, K. J., Eng, S. J. & Fessler, D. M. T. (2007) Harm, affect, and the moral/conventional distinction. Mind and Language 22:117–31. Available at: http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199733477.003.0013.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Machery, E. (2012) Delineating the moral domain. Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication 7:114. Available at: http://dx.doi.org/10.4148/biyclc.v7i0.1777.Google Scholar
Machery, E. (2018) Morality: A historical invention. In: Atlas of moral psychology, ed. Gray, K. & Graham, J., pp. 259–65. Guilford Press.Google Scholar
Machery, E. & Mallon, R. (2010) Evolution of morality. In: The moral psychology handbook, ed. Doris, J. M. &the Moral Psychology Research Group, pp. 346. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nichols, S. & Folds-Bennett, T. (2003) Are children moral objectivists? Children's judgments about moral and response-dependent properties. Cognition 90(2):B2332. Available at: http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/s0010-0277(03)00160-4.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
O'Neill, E. & Machery, E. (forthcoming) What is the normative sense? Cross cultural evidence. In: Routledge handbook of moral epistemology, ed. Zimmerman, A., Jones, K. & Timmons, M.. Routledge.Google Scholar
Sarkissian, H., Park, J., Tien, D., Wright, J. C. & Knobe, J. (2011) Folk moral relativism. Mind and Language 26:482505.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Skitka, L. J., Bauman, C. W. & Sargis, E. G. (2005) Moral conviction: Another contributor to attitude strength or something more? Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 8:895917.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Turiel, E. (1983) The development of social knowledge: Morality and convention. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Wierzbicka, A. (2007) Moral sense. Journal of Social, Evolutionary, and Cultural Psychology 1:6685.CrossRefGoogle Scholar